Serveur d'exploration autour du libre accès en Belgique

Attention, ce site est en cours de développement !
Attention, site généré par des moyens informatiques à partir de corpus bruts.
Les informations ne sont donc pas validées.

The role of the relatives in opt-in systems of postmortal organ procurement

Identifieur interne : 000167 ( Pmc/Corpus ); précédent : 000166; suivant : 000168

The role of the relatives in opt-in systems of postmortal organ procurement

Auteurs : Govert Den Hartogh

Source :

RBID : PMC:3319896

Abstract

In almost all opt-in systems of postmortal organ procurement, if the deceased has not made a decision about donation, his relatives will be asked to make it. Can this decision power be justified? I consider three possible justifications. (1) We could presume the deceased to have delegated this power to his relatives. (2) It could be argued that, if the deceased has not made a decision, a proxy decision has to be made in his best interests. (3) The relatives could have a standing of their own because they are singled out from the parties whose interests are being affected by the decision by the special relation they had to the deceased. None of these arguments turns out to be convincing.


Url:
DOI: 10.1007/s11019-011-9317-0
PubMed: 21365351
PubMed Central: 3319896

Links to Exploration step

PMC:3319896

Le document en format XML

<record>
<TEI>
<teiHeader>
<fileDesc>
<titleStmt>
<title xml:lang="en">The role of the relatives in opt-in systems of postmortal organ procurement</title>
<author>
<name sortKey="Den Hartogh, Govert" sort="Den Hartogh, Govert" uniqKey="Den Hartogh G" first="Govert" last="Den Hartogh">Govert Den Hartogh</name>
<affiliation>
<nlm:aff id="Aff1">Department of Philosophy, University of Amsterdam, Oude Turfmarkt 141-147, 1012 GC Amsterdam, The Netherlands</nlm:aff>
</affiliation>
</author>
</titleStmt>
<publicationStmt>
<idno type="wicri:source">PMC</idno>
<idno type="pmid">21365351</idno>
<idno type="pmc">3319896</idno>
<idno type="url">http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3319896</idno>
<idno type="RBID">PMC:3319896</idno>
<idno type="doi">10.1007/s11019-011-9317-0</idno>
<date when="2011">2011</date>
<idno type="wicri:Area/Pmc/Corpus">000167</idno>
</publicationStmt>
<sourceDesc>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<title xml:lang="en" level="a" type="main">The role of the relatives in opt-in systems of postmortal organ procurement</title>
<author>
<name sortKey="Den Hartogh, Govert" sort="Den Hartogh, Govert" uniqKey="Den Hartogh G" first="Govert" last="Den Hartogh">Govert Den Hartogh</name>
<affiliation>
<nlm:aff id="Aff1">Department of Philosophy, University of Amsterdam, Oude Turfmarkt 141-147, 1012 GC Amsterdam, The Netherlands</nlm:aff>
</affiliation>
</author>
</analytic>
<series>
<title level="j">Medicine, Health Care, and Philosophy</title>
<idno type="ISSN">1386-7423</idno>
<idno type="eISSN">1572-8633</idno>
<imprint>
<date when="2011">2011</date>
</imprint>
</series>
</biblStruct>
</sourceDesc>
</fileDesc>
<profileDesc>
<textClass></textClass>
</profileDesc>
</teiHeader>
<front>
<div type="abstract" xml:lang="en">
<p>In almost all opt-in systems of postmortal organ procurement, if the deceased has not made a decision about donation, his relatives will be asked to make it. Can this decision power be justified? I consider three possible justifications. (1) We could presume the deceased to have delegated this power to his relatives. (2) It could be argued that, if the deceased has not made a decision, a proxy decision has to be made in his best interests. (3) The relatives could have a standing of their own because they are singled out from the parties whose interests are being affected by the decision by the special relation they had to the deceased. None of these arguments turns out to be convincing.</p>
</div>
</front>
<back>
<div1 type="bibliography">
<listBibl>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Anderson, Joel" uniqKey="Anderson J">Joel Anderson</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Honneth, Axel" uniqKey="Honneth A">Axel Honneth</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Bell, Mddominic" uniqKey="Bell M">MDDominic Bell</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Boddington, Paula" uniqKey="Boddington P">Paula Boddington</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Bucklin, Leonard H" uniqKey="Bucklin L">Leonard H. Bucklin</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Cleiren, Marcphd" uniqKey="Cleiren M">MarcPHD Cleiren</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Zoelen, Ada J" uniqKey="Zoelen A">Ada J Zoelen</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct></biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Den Hartogh, Govert" uniqKey="Den Hartogh G">Govert den Hartogh</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct></biblStruct>
<biblStruct></biblStruct>
<biblStruct></biblStruct>
<biblStruct></biblStruct>
<biblStruct></biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Dubois, James M" uniqKey="Dubois J">James M. DuBois</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Eaton, S" uniqKey="Eaton S">S Eaton</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Engberts, Dp" uniqKey="Engberts D">DP Engberts</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Etzioni, Amitai" uniqKey="Etzioni A">Amitai Etzioni</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Farsides, Tom" uniqKey="Farsides T">Tom Farsides</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Feinberg, Joel" uniqKey="Feinberg J">Joel Feinberg</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Friele, Rd" uniqKey="Friele R">RD Friele</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Kerssens, Jj" uniqKey="Kerssens J">JJ Kerssens</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Gevers, S" uniqKey="Gevers S">S Gevers</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Janssen, A" uniqKey="Janssen A">A Janssen</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Friele, R" uniqKey="Friele R">R Friele</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Godbout, Jacques T" uniqKey="Godbout J">Jacques T Godbout</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Caille, Alain" uniqKey="Caille A">Alain Caillé</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Hilhorst, Medard" uniqKey="Hilhorst M">Medard Hilhorst</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Jacob, Marie" uniqKey="Jacob M">Marie Jacob</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Klassen, Ac" uniqKey="Klassen A">AC Klassen</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Klassen, Dk" uniqKey="Klassen D">DK Klassen</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Lauritzen, Paul" uniqKey="Lauritzen P">Paul Lauritzen</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Mcclure, Michael" uniqKey="Mcclure M">Michael McClure</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Smith, Martin L" uniqKey="Smith M">Martin L Smith</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Trew, Andrew" uniqKey="Trew A">Andrew Trew</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Mackenzie, Catriona" uniqKey="Mackenzie C">Catriona Mackenzie</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct></biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="May, Thomas" uniqKey="May T">Thomas May</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Aulisio, Marc P" uniqKey="Aulisio M">Marc P Aulisio</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Vita, Michael A" uniqKey="Vita M">Michael A Vita</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Mongoven, Ann" uniqKey="Mongoven A">Ann Mongoven</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Morris, Ed" uniqKey="Morris E">ED Morris</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Nationaler, Ethikrat" uniqKey="Nationaler E">Ethikrat Nationaler </name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Nowenstein, Graciela" uniqKey="Nowenstein G">Graciela Nowenstein</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Nowenstein, Graciela" uniqKey="Nowenstein G">Graciela Nowenstein</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Radeck, Cm" uniqKey="Radeck C">CM Radeck</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Jaccard, J" uniqKey="Jaccard J">J Jaccard</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Sanner, Margaret A" uniqKey="Sanner M">Margaret A Sanner</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Schenderling, J" uniqKey="Schenderling J">J Schenderling</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Siminoff, Laura A" uniqKey="Siminoff L">Laura A Siminoff</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Chillag, Kata" uniqKey="Chillag K">Kata Chillag</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Siminoff, Laura A" uniqKey="Siminoff L">Laura A Siminoff</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Mercer, Mary Beth" uniqKey="Mercer M">Mary Beth Mercer</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Graham, Gregory" uniqKey="Graham G">Gregory Graham</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Burant, Christopher" uniqKey="Burant C">Christopher Burant</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Spital, Aron" uniqKey="Spital A">Aron Spital</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Sque, Margaret Rg" uniqKey="Sque M">Margaret RG Sque</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Payne, Sheila A" uniqKey="Payne S">Sheila A Payne</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Sque, Magi" uniqKey="Sque M">Magi Sque</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Long, Tracy" uniqKey="Long T">Tracy Long</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Payne, Sheila" uniqKey="Payne S">Sheila Payne</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Allardyce, Diana" uniqKey="Allardyce D">Diana Allardyce</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Streat, Stephen" uniqKey="Streat S">Stephen Streat</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct></biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Veatch, Robert M" uniqKey="Veatch R">Robert M Veatch</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Verheyde, Jl" uniqKey="Verheyde J">JL Verheyde</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Rady, My" uniqKey="Rady M">MY Rady</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Mc Gregor, J" uniqKey="Mc Gregor J">J Mc Gregor</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Wall, Stephen P" uniqKey="Wall S">Stephen P Wall</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Dubler, Nancy N" uniqKey="Dubler N">Nancy N Dubler</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Goldfrank, Lewis R" uniqKey="Goldfrank L">Lewis R Goldfrank</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Wendler, Dave" uniqKey="Wendler D">Dave Wendler</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Dickert, Neil" uniqKey="Dickert N">Neil Dickert</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Wertheimer, Alan" uniqKey="Wertheimer A">Alan Wertheimer</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Wilkinson, T Martin" uniqKey="Wilkinson T">T Martin Wilkinson</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
</listBibl>
</div1>
</back>
</TEI>
<pmc article-type="research-article">
<pmc-dir>properties open_access</pmc-dir>
<front>
<journal-meta>
<journal-id journal-id-type="nlm-ta">Med Health Care Philos</journal-id>
<journal-id journal-id-type="iso-abbrev">Med Health Care Philos</journal-id>
<journal-title-group>
<journal-title>Medicine, Health Care, and Philosophy</journal-title>
</journal-title-group>
<issn pub-type="ppub">1386-7423</issn>
<issn pub-type="epub">1572-8633</issn>
<publisher>
<publisher-name>Springer Netherlands</publisher-name>
<publisher-loc>Dordrecht</publisher-loc>
</publisher>
</journal-meta>
<article-meta>
<article-id pub-id-type="pmid">21365351</article-id>
<article-id pub-id-type="pmc">3319896</article-id>
<article-id pub-id-type="publisher-id">9317</article-id>
<article-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1007/s11019-011-9317-0</article-id>
<article-categories>
<subj-group subj-group-type="heading">
<subject>Scientific Contribution</subject>
</subj-group>
</article-categories>
<title-group>
<article-title>The role of the relatives in opt-in systems of postmortal organ procurement</article-title>
</title-group>
<contrib-group>
<contrib contrib-type="author" corresp="yes">
<name>
<surname>den Hartogh</surname>
<given-names>Govert</given-names>
</name>
<address>
<phone>+31-235-321273</phone>
<email>G.A.denHartogh@uva.nl</email>
</address>
<xref ref-type="aff" rid="Aff1"></xref>
</contrib>
<aff id="Aff1">Department of Philosophy, University of Amsterdam, Oude Turfmarkt 141-147, 1012 GC Amsterdam, The Netherlands</aff>
</contrib-group>
<pub-date pub-type="epub">
<day>2</day>
<month>3</month>
<year>2011</year>
</pub-date>
<pub-date pub-type="pmc-release">
<day>2</day>
<month>3</month>
<year>2011</year>
</pub-date>
<pub-date pub-type="ppub">
<month>5</month>
<year>2012</year>
</pub-date>
<volume>15</volume>
<issue>2</issue>
<fpage>195</fpage>
<lpage>205</lpage>
<permissions>
<copyright-statement>© The Author(s) 2011</copyright-statement>
</permissions>
<abstract id="Abs1">
<p>In almost all opt-in systems of postmortal organ procurement, if the deceased has not made a decision about donation, his relatives will be asked to make it. Can this decision power be justified? I consider three possible justifications. (1) We could presume the deceased to have delegated this power to his relatives. (2) It could be argued that, if the deceased has not made a decision, a proxy decision has to be made in his best interests. (3) The relatives could have a standing of their own because they are singled out from the parties whose interests are being affected by the decision by the special relation they had to the deceased. None of these arguments turns out to be convincing.</p>
</abstract>
<kwd-group>
<title>Keywords</title>
<kwd>Opt-in system</kwd>
<kwd>Organ donation</kwd>
<kwd>Presumed consent</kwd>
<kwd>Proxy decision making</kwd>
<kwd>Special relations</kwd>
</kwd-group>
<custom-meta-group>
<custom-meta>
<meta-name>issue-copyright-statement</meta-name>
<meta-value>© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012</meta-value>
</custom-meta>
</custom-meta-group>
</article-meta>
</front>
<body>
<sec id="Sec1" sec-type="introduction">
<title>Introduction</title>
<p>Legal systems of the procurement of postmortal organs for transplantation are usually classified into opt-in and opt-out systems. Systems of both types aim to respect the decision of the deceased person, whether his decision is to donate or to refuse donation, or to hand over the decision to his relatives (or to some other person). The basic difference between these systems of organ procurement concerns what they take to be the
<italic>default</italic>
: what will happen when the deceased has not made any decision at all. In pure opt-in systems the default is that no removal of organs will take place, in opt-out systems that it will take place.
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn1">1</xref>
In almost all systems commonly known as opt-in systems, however, the actual default is that the decision will be made by the family of the deceased, hence a threefold classification would be more accurate than the present one.</p>
<p>In this paper I want to discuss the role of the relatives in so-called opt-in systems, where the actual default is that they decide. My basic question is whether this choice of default can be justified. As a matter of fact, however, the relatives have a similar role in opt-out systems as we know them. For in such systems the default—removal of the organs- can be defeated in two ways: by the refusal of the deceased person, registered before her death, or by the actual refusal of the family. In some cases this power of veto is recognized by the law, in other cases it isn’t, but in actual practice it is recognised virtually always and everywhere.
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn2">2</xref>
Hence that the next of kin have the last word is the most common, almost universal, feature of the existing systems of postmortal organ procurement.</p>
<p>That the relatives have the last word in all systems, however, doesn’t mean that after all there really is no difference between opt-out and opt-in systems as we know them.
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn3">3</xref>
For even for the way in which they normally use this power it may be relevant what the default is. This may be relevant in itself, but also because of the information it provides indirectly about the preferences of the deceased. (“He could have refused but he didn’t”). For that reason I will concentrate my discussion on the purest case, which is the role of the relatives in opt-in systems. Having decided whether any justification can be found for taking the decision power of the family as our default, I will then go on to consider the possible justifications of this power as a defeating consideration.</p>
<p>I do not embark on this investigation with a revisionist mind. For such a common feature one expects to be able to find a rationale and it would not be unwelcome ro find it. What I have to report, however, is failure in this respect on the whole. The only, rather modest status of the family which turns out to be justifiable is a power of veto in the one kind of opt-out system which can claim to satisfy fully the requirement of consent (Sect. “
<xref rid="Sec7" ref-type="sec">First conclusion: the vain pretentions of opt-in systems</xref>
”).</p>
</sec>
<sec id="Sec2">
<title>Possible strategies of justification</title>
<p>In considering the possibilities of justifying a decision-making power of the relatives within the framework of opt-in systems, we can start by noticing an obvious objection to attributing any such power to them. The common presupposition of the opt-in systems is that,
<italic>ceteris paribus</italic>
, nothing can be done to the body of a person, not even her dead body, without her consent. Indeed, this is often, albeit mistakenly, supposed to be an implication of the basic human right to bodily integrity. (Wilkinson
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR47">2007</xref>
).
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn4">4</xref>
My right to dispose of my own body follows from the special relation that exists between me and my body, a relation which fundamentally changes, but does not end with my death. It changes because I am no longer co-existent with my body, but it does not end because as a living person I have a special stake in what happens to my body after my death, for example that it will be treated with respect. It is basically a negative, not a positive right: it prohibits other people to do things with my body without my consent, but it doesn’t give me the power to claim positive efforts from them.</p>
<p>If, however, my relatives are allowed to permit the removal of my organs after my death when I have not made any explicit decision about this matter at all before I died, such decisions seem to violate the requirement of consent.</p>
<p>The same objection can of course be made to opt-out systems as such. This objection can be and has been met in three different ways, which, it will turn out, are possibly available in an analogous way for defending the decision powers of the family in opt-in systems.</p>
<p>The three ways of defending opt-out systems differ in the importance they attribute to the requirement of consent. According to the first justification the requirement of consent can be overridden by other important countervailing interests. This is recognized by all legal systems which permit post-mortem autopsies of bodies, on the orders of some legal authority, in the interests of criminal justice, without prior consent. It could be argued that the requirement can equally well be overridden by the urgent interests of patients suffering from organ failure in receiving organs for transplantation. In that case the availability of the opt-out option can be seen as a kind of compromise: even if the system doesn’t require consent, it stops short of relying on coercion. In that respect it still differs fundamentally from conscription systems.
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn5">5</xref>
</p>
<p>According to the second and third justification of opt–out systems there is no need to override the requirement of consent. According to the second justification the requirement can be satisfied. For even if consent has not actually been given, it can at least be ‘presumed’, if the opt-out option has not been used. In the English-speaking world opt-out systems of organ procurement are even usually referred to as ‘presumed consent’ systems. This is unfortunate, for it overlooks the possibility of the first and third justification. The first justification as a matter of fact may have been the most prominent justifying ground for the introduction of such systems in most European countries.</p>
<p>Whether or not a presumed consent defence is available for opt-out systems, turns out to depend on the proper conception of ‘consent’. According to some theorists consent is basically a mental state: to consent to some action means to prefer it to all feasible alternatives. On this conception it makes sense to provide evidence of what a person would have preferred, if she is no longer there to tell us. On the alternative conception of consent it is a public act of authorisation which gives another person a right to do something which he hadn’t before. To consent is to publicly exercise a power of authority in determining other peoples’ rights and duties. On this conception consent can only actually be given, not presumed. If no proper act of authorization has taken place, consent has not been given, whatever we may infer, and infer correctly, about the preferences of the agent. I have elsewhere defended a public act conception of consent, and will presuppose in this paper that it provides us with a decisive argument against presuming consent (den Hartogh (forthcoming); cf. Wertheimer
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR46">2003</xref>
).</p>
<p>According to the third justification it can be allowed that to consent is to publicly exercise an authority. However, situations may arise in which it is impossible for a person to exercise her authority. An exemplary case occurs when a person is transferred to a hospital in a comatose condition after a stroke or an accident, and we have to decide whether or not to reanimate her. We can no longer ask her what we should do, hence we have no alternative but to attempt to act in her best interests as we can best ascertain these to be. In such a case we are not overriding the requirement of consent; it simply doesn’t stand in our way (den Hartogh submitted).
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn6">6</xref>
</p>
<p>These three strategies of defending opt-out systems can analogously be used for justifying the decision power of the next of kin in opt-in systems. I will consider all three of them, beginning with the second strategy (Sect. “
<xref rid="Sec3" ref-type="sec">Presumed delegation</xref>
”), and then proceeding to the third (Sect. “
<xref rid="Sec4" ref-type="sec">Donation by procuration?</xref>
”) and the first (Sects. “
<xref rid="Sec5" ref-type="sec">A gift from the next of kin?</xref>
” and “
<xref rid="Sec6" ref-type="sec">The weakest party</xref>
”).</p>
</sec>
<sec id="Sec3">
<title>Presumed delegation</title>
<p>Opt-in systems presuppose that your rights over your own body make it unacceptable to take your organs without your consent. But if that is correct, how should we judge opt-in systems as we know them? As we saw in Sect. “
<xref rid="Sec1" ref-type="sec">Introduction</xref>
”, almost no country in the world has a pure opt-in system
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn7">7</xref>
: if you have not registered any decision, your relatives will be asked to make the decision in your place. How can we justify this power? In particular, how can we reconcile it with your right to make decisions concerning your own dead body? The only remotely plausible way seems to be: by presuming that people who make no decision themselves, consent to the decision to be made by their relatives. From this perspective the existing opt-in systems themselves turn out to be a kind of presumed consent systems. What they ‘presume’ is consent to delegation: a person does not himself lift the barrier blocking access to his private domain, but he authorizes someone else to lift it.</p>
<p>Such systems are open to the same objection to presuming consent that I mentioned in Sect. “
<xref rid="Sec2" ref-type="sec">Possible strategies of justification</xref>
”.
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn8">8</xref>
Presumed consent is false money, for what it presumes is only preference, and preference is not consent. It is a remarkable fact about the organ donation debate that so many authors (and parliamentarians) criticize presumed consent systems, often vehemently, as being incompatible with ‘the right to self-determination’, without noticing that the system they support is vulnerable to the very same basic objection.
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn9">9</xref>
It is based on a counterfeit.</p>
<p>Actually the legal situation is often even worse. The argument of this section concerns opt-in systems which give each person a number of options to choose from, including the option of refusal, and only presume delegation if she doesn’t make use of any of those options. But many of the so-called opt-in systems we know do not even satisfy this description. In the UK, in Ireland and in some Swiss cantons it is relatively easy to register consent, in a Donor Register or by filling in a donor card, but it is much more difficult to register refusal, which might require a living will, signed in the presence of witnesses. In the United States both donor cards and state registries usually have the same limited range of options, although in most states one can also tick yes or no on one’s driver’s license. In some US states, moreover, hospital teams just have to make a reasonable effort to discover a registered will or locate next of kin: if the efforts are unsuccessful, they are free to proceed as they wish (Morris
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR29">2002</xref>
).</p>
<p>Such systems violate everyone’s right to decide about their own bodies, including even the right of those who register their willingness to donate. Your right is, justifiedly or not, not fully respected if non-removing of organs is not taken to be the default, but your right is even less respected if it is made difficult for you to register refusal at all. In a system in which refusal would not be assumed as the default and could not be registered at all, consent would lose all meaning. In terms of your authority-right such a system would really be on a par with a conscription system, since it would depend on the will of other people whether your organs would be taken or not.</p>
<p>The same of course is true of a procurement practice in which, whatever the law says, the next of kin can effectively decide to donate, even if the decision of the deceased to refuse donation is recorded on a valid document. This is reported to be the practice of no less than 43% of the American organ procurement organizations (Wendler and Dickert
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR45">2001</xref>
).</p>
</sec>
<sec id="Sec4">
<title>Donation by procuration?</title>
<p>It is often suggested that the relatives have a
<italic>proxy</italic>
right to decide in cases in which no decision of the deceased is known—they are donors by procuration. In that case they would be duty-bound to make the decision they think he would have made. The suggestion is implied by another argument which has often been made, for example by the legislator of the Dutch Law on the Donation of Organs of 1998. According to this argument opinion surveys show that many more people are actually prepared to donate than have registered a positive decision. In order to create the opportunity that the positive attitude of these people will be acted upon, we give their relatives the right to consent to the taking of the organs. It is obvious that this argument presupposes that the relatives will decide in the spirit of the deceased. They are supposed to be
<italic>delegates</italic>
.
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn10">10</xref>
The case, as I pointed out in Sect.
<xref rid="Sec2" ref-type="sec">Possible strategies of justification</xref>
, can be compared to the situation arising when a decision has to be made about medical treatment of a patient who is unable to consent himself. In that case many legal systems give a right of proxy decision making to his relatives.</p>
<p>However, such situations differ from the present one in two respects. If a person gets unconscious as a result of an accident, there is usually no time at which he is able to make a decision concerning his treatment himself. He may only be able
<italic>ex ante</italic>
to provide general instructions, for example about resuscitation, which necessarily leave a large scope for interpretation. (May et al.
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR27">2000</xref>
, 326–327) Moreover, as a matter of fact no legal system requires to ask people to make such an
<italic>ex ante</italic>
decision. But in most opt-in systems (at least in North America and Europe) the government actively invites all citizens to register a decision, in a national Donor Register, on a donor card, on a driving licence, or in other ways. If such countries had a pure opt-in system, in which not taking the organs would be the default, they might still have the same mechanisms for consent, albeit not for refusal. In that case every adult person would have all the opportunity he needs to express his consent, or his delegation of the decision to others, and there would not be any need for proxy-decision making at all. Hence that supposed need cannot be a good reason for choosing another default. Similarly, if a person has made no will, on his death we dispose of his inheritance in accordance with default rules provided by the law; we would not consider asking his relatives whether he might have preferred to deviate from those rules.</p>
<p>In the second place, we should ask why so many people do fail to register a preference. Some people are not sufficiently interested in the issue to spend time on making up their minds; in particular, they don’t want to be confronted with their own mortality. A much larger number of people are unable to make up their minds. Yes, they are in favour of transplantation medicine because of the extent to which it improves patients’ chances of survival and their welfare. But this rather abstract general attitude is counterbalanced by a number of doubts concerning their own individual cases: the burden for the relatives, some mistrust of doctors, the wish to leave the dead body intact for some time, and more or less vague religious objections. Interestingly, these doubts tend to be expressed, not as beliefs to which one clearly subscribes, but only as ‘feelings’. (Taels and van Raaij
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR41">2008</xref>
)
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn11">11</xref>
So it seems that the very failure to register normally indicates either indifference or ambivalence. The person either wasn’t interested in making a decision, or unable to make it because of conflicting considerations. If that is the case, by asking her relatives to decide in her spirit we are asking for the impossible. Her spirit has been characterized by indifference or ambivalence, so it can be represented neither by consent nor by refusal. It could be better represented by tossing a coin than by asking the relatives.</p>
<p>So from the point of view of people’s right to decide about their own bodies, the idea of proxy decision-making is doubly problematic: there is no need to give anyone that task, and it is normally an impossible task to execute.
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn12">12</xref>
Moreover, although many relatives earnestly try to decide in the spirit of the deceased, the significant extent to which, as we know, their decision actually is determined by other considerations provides us with an additional reason not to entrust them with this problematic task. If the family refuses to permit the refusal of the organs because they have not been treated with sufficient concern and respect by medical staff, they are, however, understandably, punishing the wrong people.
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn13">13</xref>
</p>
<p>In many cases families apparently refuse to consent to donation because they believe that they have no right to dispose of the deceased’s organs if he hasn’t given his consent personally (Eaton
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR8">1998</xref>
; Nationaler Ethikrat
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR10">2007</xref>
, 24).
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn14">14</xref>
For them the requirement of consent means that refusal is the default. But that is the very position the lawgiver wanted to avoid by empowering them to make a proxy-decision. Obviously the lawgiver fears that a pure opt-in system would substantially reduce the number of organs available for transplantation even in comparison with the present situation of pressing scarcity. But it is doubtful whether that problem really is surmounted by supplementing the system with proxy decision-making. Instead of accepting refusal to be the default, the system asks the relatives to reconsider, but in a context in which
<italic>they</italic>
naturally continue considering refusal to be the default. People who find it difficult to arrive at a decision may be all too happy to leave it to their next-of-kin, but they only inherit the problem and may ‘solve’ it in a similar way. “They seem[ed] to regard ‘no’ as a non-decision” (Sanner
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR33">2007</xref>
; cf. Siminoff et al.
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR36">2007</xref>
).</p>
</sec>
<sec id="Sec5">
<title>A gift from the next of kin?</title>
<p>If the decision power of the family cannot be derived from the authority or the interests of the deceased, this leaves us with only one option for justifying that power: the relatives could have a proper standing of their own. Their decision-power on that view is not to be derived from the authority people have over their own dead bodies, neither by presuming consent nor by supplementing it by proxy-decision making.</p>
<p>Which arguments could we provide in favour of this independent authority? It is sometimes suggested that the requirement of consent rests on an individualistic model of decision-making which is not really accepted by people, even in an individualistic society: most people who register a decision do so on the basis of collective deliberation with their relatives, and it is the same group, the family, who as such is making the final decision when the person has died. (Boddington
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR3">1998</xref>
, in a tentative way; Lauritzen et al.
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR23">2001</xref>
) Hence we should not consider the individual rights of the deceased but the group right of his family. But this argument confuses the power to decide with a “model of decision-making”. There is not the slightest inconsistency in a person having the power to make a certain decision and her actually doing so in close consultation with others or even delegating the decision to them. We need not deny that agents are neither self-reliant nor self-transparent, and hence in their decision-making necessarily depend on others in all kinds of ways (explored in the literature on relational autonomy, as summarized in Mackenzie and Stoljar
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR25">2000</xref>
) in order to go on insisting that certain decisions are up to the agents themselves and not to those others. A recognition of the social embeddedness of ‘autonomous’ agents does not commit one to hold only families and other groups to be empowered to make decisions regarding those agents. Occasionally the family is reported to decide to which of its (usually junior) members the task is assigned of donating a living kidney to another family member in need of it, but we consider this objectionable bceause it makes the individual into a mere means for the promotion of the collective interests of the family. So, even if we accept that people normally make such decisions, to register as a donor or to refuse registering, in consultation with their relatives, we are still in need of a justification of the independent authority of the family when no such decision has been made.</p>
<p>To start with, we could point out that donation usually demands a greater sacrifice from the next of kin than from the donor. At a moment that they are still in shock about the incident which took the life of their partner or child, they see their loved one taken into the operating theatre while he does not yet look as if he is dead, and have to wait until he returns in the shape of a real dead body. Sometimes they have to wait for this during the time that artificial respiration is continued until brain death has been confirmed. And they subsequently have to live with the memory of the whole course of events. (Klassen and Klassen
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR22">1996</xref>
; Mongoven
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR28">2003</xref>
, 92) “The true gift comes from the family” (Siminoff and Chillag
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR35">1999</xref>
; cf. Lauritzen et al.
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR23">2001</xref>
).</p>
<p>A first question about this view is whether it does sufficient justice to the point of view of the relatives themselves. Generally speaking, their main concern is what the deceased would have wished. And even if they then consciously decide otherwise, they do not usually do this because they are giving priority to their own interests, but, for example, because they want to protect the deceased’s body and thereby his ‘person’ in a certain sense (Sque et al.
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR39">2008</xref>
). Insofar as the next of kin are able and willing to bear responsibility for the decision, therefore, they mainly focus on the deceased’s interests as they see them at that moment. They do not claim their personal interests to be protected by their authority.</p>
<p>This does not alter the fact that the deceased’s interests are also
<italic>their</italic>
interests. It could seriously encumber their bereavement and grief process if they felt afterwards that they had failed their loved one at such a crucial moment. However, if we allow them to have an interest which requires to be protected by rights which overrides the authority of the deceased, they are not the only ones who may have such interests. We have also to consider the interests of the patients suffering from organ failure and waiting for a donor organ, and it can hardly be denied that these interests are greater. Transplantation for them may make the difference between life and death, or between a relatively normal and a miserable life. Even when we take into account the possibility of failure of the operation and the adverse side-effects from the immunosuppressants necessary for survival, the overall balance is clear.</p>
<p>But, it could be argued, it is not only a question of who has the greater interests, for the next of kin have special ties with the deceased that also entail special mutual care and responsibility for one another’s needs. This special relationship gives those involved the right to concern themselves more with each other’s interests than with those of anonymous strangers. It could be argued that this special relationship still has this significance when one of the people involved in it has died, which is why it is proper to give the next of kin priority over potential recipients of the deceased’s organs. They are being asked to make a sacrifice, and they are the ones to decide whether or not they wish to make it.
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn15">15</xref>
</p>
<p>This seems to be the basic argument for the independent authority of the relatives. How should we assess it? Both of the premises on which it is based are indisputable: the next of kin have a genuine interest in the decision on donation, and they (usually) have a special relationship with the deceased. And I do not at all wish to deny that this special relationship has a moral significance. In his
<italic>Enquiry concerning Political Justice</italic>
(1793), William Godwin, the founding father of both utilitarianism and anarchism, discusses the dilemma facing me if I am only able to rescue one person from a house on fire: either Archbishop Fénelon (a philosopher who Godwin greatly admired), or his chambermaid, who also happens to be my wife, mother or benefactress. According to Godwin, it is a requirement of ‘pure, unadulterated justice’ to save the philosopher: “What magic is there in the pronoun ‘my’, to overturn the decisions of everlasting truth? My wife or my mother may be a fool or a prostitute, malicious, lying or dishonest. If they be, of what consequence is it that they are mine?” However, anyone seriously able to subscribe in this way to an impartial principle is not capable of forming close intimate relationships. Therefore, we are not to be criticised for giving particular care and attention to people with whom we have a special relationship; on the contrary, if we did not do this we would demonstrate that we have no sense of the true significance of this relationship. The simple pronoun ‘my’ does indeed have magic.
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn16">16</xref>
That, indeed, may be the moral basis of the whole practice of living donation. (Hilhorst
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR21">2005</xref>
).</p>
<p>But is this a sufficient reason for allowing the next of kin to decide? There are two reasons to have doubts. In the first place, even if we allow the special claims implied by special relationships, it does not follow that they simply eclipse all other claims. Let us grant that the donor may multiply his own interests and those of the people with whom he has a special relationship by a given factor before he weighs up these interests against the recipient’s needs. The moral magic of the pronoun ‘my’ is in that case already included in the criteria for the existence of a duty to help others in an emergency. This corresponds to the common understanding of the duty as it has been classically expressed by Thomas Aquinas: “Those who fail to give a gift are in danger of committing a mortal sin: from the recipient’s point of view, if a clear and urgent need becomes apparent and no helper appears and from the giver’s point of view, if he can spare that which is not necessary to him in view of his present situation…” (
<italic>Summa Theologiae</italic>
, 2ae, q. 32, a. 5, quoted from Schenderling
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR34">2003</xref>
) Even on this loaded weighing of interests, the needs of the patients seem paramount. After all, research has shown that the donation process has no lasting psychological consequences for the surviving relatives, not even if they have doubts about the donation afterwards. (Cleiren and van Zoelen
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR5">2002</xref>
).</p>
<p>Moreover, our duties vis-à-vis the patients may not be exhaustively described by conceiving of them as duties of rescue. For everyone of us can during his lifetime get organ failure to an extent at which he can only be helped by a transplantation, and therefore everyone of us benefits from the existence through time of a pool of organs available for that end, by the assurance it provides of assistance in a possible future emergency (Cleiren and Van Zoelen
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR5">2002</xref>
). Contributing to that pool therefore means participating in a collaborative arrangement for mutual benefit, and therefore could be seen as an obligation of fairness.
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn17">17</xref>
And special care relationships are not taken into account in forms of cooperation for mutual benefit in which contributions and profits are directly coordinated. Those who voluntarily contribute less have fewer rights: the reasons why they contribute less are not important. We cannot evade our duty to participate in dyke surveillance during a gale on the grounds that the gale also poses a threat to our bicycle sheds or those of our children or neighbours.</p>
<p>So even if we agree that the relatives have relevant interests and their interests should generally be given extra weight because of their special relationship to the deceased, it does not follow that these interests should be given priority in this particular case. Even if we only have duties of rescue to the patients with organ failure, their interests seem to deserve priority. If, in addition, we have duties of fairness to them, their interests need only be weighier than those of the relatives to be paramount. And they are.</p>
<p>It could be objected that this counterargument only shows that the relatives should use their authority to decide by giving priority to the interests of the recipients, not that they don’t have the authority. This brings me to the second reason why the present argument for the independent status of the relatives fails. The appeal to their interests, and the additional weight those interests acquire from their special relationship to the deceased, does not establish that they have any authority. Dead bodies are not usually considered to be property that can be inherited. But even if proprietary rights to dead bodies were to pass to family members through inheritance, the duties we have discussed would still be attached to these rights. It is true that, even if it is allowed that these duties exist, it is an open question to what extent they should be regarded as enforceable. If they should not, we would have the right to refuse to register as a donor despite the fact that this decision is liable to moral criticism. However, the same cannot apply to our next of kin. Even if we had the right to set aside our duty for the sake of their interests, it does not follow that they also have the right to set aside our duty for the sake of their own interests. The interests of the family are a consideration to be given its proper weight, but it does not follow that they are protected by rights and powers of decision. (Wilkinson
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR47">2007</xref>
, 34).</p>
<p>Suppose it did follow. In that case the relatives would be entitled to this position of authority because a greater sacrifice is required from them than from the deceased himself. But if that were the case, the relatives should also be entitled to veto the deceased’s own decision to register as a donor. This kind of double veto is legally recognised in countries such as Great Britain. However, it is widely accepted, and in some countries, including the USA and the Netherlands, legally established that registering a willingness to donate not only means that consent has been given for donation, but also that the relatives must respect this consent.
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn18">18</xref>
In that event, the relatives cannot invoke the special relationship they had with the deceased. But this means that they cannot directly derive any right to decide from this special relationship, since they would then be able to exercise this right with respect to the deceased, too. If the special relationship does have any significance, this is only because the deceased conferred this significance on it before his death. He must have done so explicitly. If the next of kin are only entitled to the right to decide because the deceased has conferred this right on them, default cannot lie in delegation.</p>
</sec>
<sec id="Sec6">
<title>The weakest party</title>
<p>There is one more argument in favour of this placement of the default that I would like to discuss, in particular because it sheds an interesting light on the meaning of default as such. Choosing the default is of immense importance in contract law. Marie Jacob has interestingly pointed out that the default in that domain is often determined in such a way as to protect the interests of the party with the weakest negotiating position. The reason is that if the other party wants to depart from the default, he will be obliged to open explicit negotiations in this respect, which will invariably involve additional costs. (Jacob
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR26">2006</xref>
).</p>
<p>Jacob is of the opinion that in the case of organ donation, the patients in need of help have a stronger negotiating position than the deceased.
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn19">19</xref>
But she entirely disregards the position of the family in the issue. In practice, all over the world the next-of-kin have the last word, and if only for this reason, the question of which party’s negotiating position should be strengthened should primarily be considered in relation to relatives and patients. Of these two parties, patients waiting for an organ are clearly in the weaker position. All they can do is wait and see which way the decision will go, whereas the next of kin can make their voices heard there and then. As long as their relative is still alive, they are entitled to information on his treatment. If this relative is not a registered donor, in many jurisdictions their permission already has to be obtained in the case of preparatory measures for the preservation of the organs. Furthermore, the next of kin are in such a difficult situation anyway that we dislike the idea of confronting them with the additional burden of asking them to consent to donation. (As well as with all the relevant information that may be highly confusing, such as the concept of ‘brain death’.) Given the situation, it is almost in bad taste to point out their moral duties to them, whether or not such duties exist. In many cases, the doctors who ask for their consent have just had to relinquish their efforts to save their partner or child, and rightly feel jointly responsible for ensuring that the family are able to come to terms with this death as much as possible.
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn20">20</xref>
All these circumstances contribute towards giving their interests at least the weight they deserve to be given, and probably more.</p>
<p>It follows from this argument that we can even recommend transferring the default to ‘donation’,
<italic>without</italic>
invoking the moral desirability of donation, let alone any moral duties. If we ask ourselves how the interests of all parties concerned are actually weighed up in the decision-making process, we see that patients waiting for an organ run the greatest risk of insufficient justice being done to their interests. This also emerges from the actual results of the process, with its alarming rates of family refusal.</p>
<p>Even if there were a reason for allowing the next of kin to decide if the deceased himself has not registered any decision, this does not mean that we should deliberately keep this option open. The whole idea that we not only ask the next of kin for a gift simply because we have no choice, but even make a point of seeking the opportunity to be able to do so, is highly problematic. It is preferable to refrain from asking people for help in an emergency if these people themselves are in dire straits: this is not fair to either the givers or the recipients (Spital
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR37">1996</xref>
).
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn21">21</xref>
For this reason alone, we should prefer systems in which the decision is made in advance, in terms of the consent of the deceased or the needs of the recipients, or some combination of these considerations.</p>
</sec>
<sec id="Sec7">
<title>First conclusion: the vain pretentions of opt-in systems</title>
<p>Opt-in systems claim to respect the requirement of consent, which they hold to be implied by the authority of people in regard to their own bodies, including their dead bodies. This is the basic justification of such systems, in all countries which resist the introduction of opt-out systems, in spite of the evidence that these yield better results, in terms of the number of postmortal organs becoming available for transplantation.</p>
<p>It is true that opt-out systems as we know them are not fully compatible with the requirement of consent. But exactly the same is true for almost all opt-in systems, and for exactly the same reason. When no legally valid decision of the deceased has been registered and the next of kin decide nevertheless to donate, the requirement is violated even if the decision is made in the spirit of the deceased. For in such cases no actual consent has been given, and there is no need for supplementing actual consent by proxy consent. No-one who accepts such systems can consistently object to opt-out systems. As we have seen, some opt-in systems are even guilty of more grave violations of the requirement than at least some opt-out systems, because they make it more difficult either to have one’s refusal of donation registered, or one’s registration effective.</p>
<p>There is an additional point to be made which reinforces this conclusion. The requirement of consent is supposedly implied by the right to make decisions about one’s own body, even after one’s death. But the number of options you are actually given to choose from is extremely limited. You can decide to be buried or to be cremated, you can perhaps present your body to be used in medical education, and you can be a donor. That’s about it. You cannot normally decide to have your body mummified and set up in the hall of your
<italic>alma mater</italic>
, you are not allowed to be laid down in a small boat to be delivered to the infinite ocean, and you cannot give permission for your mortal remains to be fed to the tigers in the zoo. Most of these limitations are uncontroversial because they follow from the harm principle: dead bodies left alone are a danger for everyone coming into contact with them. Other limitations are be justified on the offence principle: they forbid actions which are supposed to show a lack of respect, not only for your person but for humanity as such. This is also the main reason given for the strict prohibition to give your body or part of it to others on condition of any valuable reward.
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn22">22</xref>
But in addition to these limitations, in most countries the only conditions you can stipulate for being a postmortal donor concern the specific organs you permit to be removed. You are not allowed to limit the class of possible recipients, either to a person or to a class of persons, not even to a harmless class like children. In this respect your position is that of an individual seller facing a monopsonistic buyer. You are being offered a standard form, and your options are only to sign or not to sign.</p>
<p>These limitations of your authority-right need to be justified. It may be possible to provide such justifications for each limitation, but then it may equally be possible to justify taking out organs as the default, even if that would involve another limitation. If one category of limitations cannot simply be blocked by appealing to our ‘right of self-determination’, neither can the other. People who reject opt-out systems as infringing their right but accept that organs cannot be sold and donation cannot be directed, owe us an explanation why this particular inroad on that right is so different from all the others.
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn23">23</xref>
</p>
<p>If we insist on the requirement of consent for organ donation, opt-in systems as we know them are equally incompatible with that requirement as opt-out systems as we know them. However, it may be possible to design an opt-out system in such a way that it is fully compatible with the requirement of consent, and in that case the same is true about a system in which delegation to the family is the default. In such systems every inhabitant of the country who has not registered a decision is clearly and regularly informed of what will happen when she dies leaving organs suitable for transplantation: removal of the organs (in the case of an opt-out system), or a decision by the family. And, as second condition, it must be easy for everyone to change her registration, by filling out a short form, and sending it postfree or online to the registration office.
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn24">24</xref>
If a person does not use that option, we are allowed to take her to give her consent to acting as the default prescribes: that is not a presumed but a tacit consent, and tacit consent can be genuine actual consent (den Hartogh (forthcoming 2)).</p>
<p>In the present climate of opinion in countries accustomed to an opt-in system and its (false) claims, a suitably modest proposal might be to introduce as the default in such a system of tacit consent that the organs will be removed unless the family persistently objects. It may be true that this is acceptable anyhow to the majority of people who do not explicitly consent. That fact, as I argued, is not enough by itself to warrant concluding that they (“presumedly”) consent to delegation, but under the conditions stated it may justify a legal provision to that effect. For within limits of reasonableness and fairness the law can stipulate what counts as consent. That system has two advantages in comparison to the usual opt-in systems: it always provides the relatives with at least some information about the preferences of the deceased, and it legitimizes approaching the relatives in a non-neutral way, asking them to give reasons for their objection, not for their consent.
<xref ref-type="fn" rid="Fn25">25</xref>
</p>
<p>It may even be possible to offer a more principled justification for this approach by appealing to the social embeddedness of autonomous decision-making. In the literature on relational autonomy it is suggested that a necessary (or at least a supporting) condition for such decision-making is that the agent has some particular attitudes towards himself, attitudes of self-esteem and self-trust, and that a necessary (or at least a supporting) condition for such attitudes to persist is social recognition of the agent by others, in particular by his close relatives and associates. (Mackenzie
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR24">2008</xref>
; Anderson and Honneth
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR1">2005</xref>
) In order to maintain the social relations needed for autonomous decision-making people therefore would justifiedly prefer to be supported in the major decisions they make as regards their own life by their relatives, and this preference tends to give these relatives some informal standing in the decision-making process. If this is correct, it does not justify ascribing a formal standing to the relatives irrespective of the agent’s actual consent, but it may justify giving such a standing a default status in the legal recognition of a form of tacit consent.</p>
</sec>
<sec id="Sec8">
<title>Second conclusion: the role of the relatives</title>
<p>If, on the other hand, it is accepted that the requirement of consent is not absolute, it does not follow that your next of kin could be given the power to decide whether or not to allow the removal of your organs for transplantation when you have died. For it cannot be shown that the interests of the relatives have a greater moral weight than the urgent needs of patients waiting for an organ.</p>
<p>Undoubtedly the relatives have special interests in what happens to the body of the deceased. The donation procedure interferes in complicated ways with the process of taking leave, and they are the ones who have to live on with the memory of that process. That is why the procedure should be adapted optimally to their needs, and why they should be properly informed about the procedure and be given adequate support during it. But it is hard to see how even the maximal protection of these needs could imply a power to decide about donation, overruling the claims of the patients on the waiting list. It may even be true that in requesting them to decide we unnecessarily create an additional burden for them.</p>
<p>So how do we explain the almost universal grant of at least a power of veto to the relatives? It is often pointed out that an overruling of substantial resistance of the next of kin would risk creating a scandal in the media which could do great harm to the general willingness to donate. But this presupposes already the general feeling that such resistance has a claim to be respected, and it is that feeling which is in need of a justification.</p>
<p>I have not been able to find this justification. My provisional conclusion therefore is that the fact that next of kin are granted the last word in so many countries, sometimes contrary to statutory regulations, is not based on an adequate moral justification, but on the sole fact of their presence on the scene and the special consideration for their circumstances required at that moment. (May et al.
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR27">2000</xref>
; Bucklin
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR4">2002</xref>
) “T)heir state of mourning gives them the right to oppose the harvesting of the newly dead.” (Nowenstein
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR30">2005</xref>
, 181, summarizing the views of French intensivists) The doctors who make the request, usually the intensive care physicians who have been responsible for the treatment of the deceased as well, rightly feel a role conflict between their traditional role of providing as much comfort to the relatives as possible and the duty to make the request. This role conflict often causes them to shy away from upsetting the relatives by “begging for body parts” (Sanner
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR33">2007</xref>
).</p>
<p>Even if no justification can be found, we should perhaps regretfully permit transplant doctors to abandon the removal of suitable organs if the relatives have strong unsurmountable objections to it. But that will be done out of consideration for their distress, in a situation in which they already have to cope with the (often sudden) death of their partner, child or sibling, and in full awareness of the wrong we thereby do to patients suffering from organ failure. It should not be done in recognition of a right to decide.</p>
</sec>
</body>
<back>
<ack>
<title>Open Access</title>
<p>This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution Noncommercial License which permits any noncommercial use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author(s) and source are credited.</p>
</ack>
<ref-list id="Bib1">
<title>References</title>
<ref id="CR1">
<mixed-citation publication-type="book">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Anderson</surname>
<given-names>Joel</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Honneth</surname>
<given-names>Axel</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<person-group person-group-type="editor">
<name>
<surname>Christman</surname>
<given-names>John</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Anderson</surname>
<given-names>Joel</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Autonomy, vulnerability, recognition, and justice</article-title>
<source>Autonomy and the challenges to liberalism</source>
<year>2005</year>
<publisher-loc>Cambridge</publisher-loc>
<publisher-name>Cambridge University Press</publisher-name>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR2">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Bell</surname>
<given-names>MDDominic</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>The UK human tissue act and consent: Surrendering a fundamental principle to transplantation needs?</article-title>
<source>Journal of Medical Ethics</source>
<year>2006</year>
<volume>32</volume>
<fpage>283</fpage>
<lpage>286</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1136/jme.2005.012666</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">16648279</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR3">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Boddington</surname>
<given-names>Paula</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Organ donation after death–Should i decide, or should my family?</article-title>
<source>Journal of Applied Philosophy</source>
<year>1998</year>
<volume>15</volume>
<fpage>69</fpage>
<lpage>81</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1111/1468-5930.00074</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR4">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Bucklin</surname>
<given-names>Leonard H.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Woe unto those who request consent: Ethical and legal considerations in rejecting a deceased anatomical gift because there is no consent by the survivors</article-title>
<source>North Dakota Law Review</source>
<year>2002</year>
<volume>78</volume>
<fpage>323</fpage>
<lpage>354</lpage>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR5">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Cleiren</surname>
<given-names>MarcPHD</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Zoelen</surname>
<given-names>Ada J</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Post-mortem organ donation and grief: A study of consent, refusal and well-being in bereavement</article-title>
<source>Death Studies</source>
<year>2002</year>
<volume>26</volume>
<fpage>837</fpage>
<lpage>839</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1080/07481180290106607</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">12440423</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR6">
<mixed-citation publication-type="other">Coördinatiegroep Orgaandonatie. (2008).
<italic>Masterplan Orgaandonatie.</italic>
den Haag.</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR17">
<mixed-citation publication-type="book">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>den Hartogh</surname>
<given-names>Govert</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<source>Mutual expectations: A conventionalist theory of law</source>
<year>2002</year>
<publisher-loc>The Hague</publisher-loc>
<publisher-name>Kluwer</publisher-name>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR18">
<mixed-citation publication-type="other">den Hartogh, Govert (2008).
<italic>Farewell to non</italic>
-
<italic>commitment.</italic>
den Haag: Raad voor de Zorg. Accessible online:
<ext-link ext-link-type="uri" xlink:href="http://www.ceg.nl/data/file/Engelse%20versie%20Afscheid%20van%20de%20vrijblijvendheid.pdf">http://www.ceg.nl/data/file/Engelse%20versie%20Afscheid%20van%20de%20vrijblijvendheid.pdf</ext-link>
.</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR48">
<mixed-citation publication-type="other">den Hartogh, Govert. 2011. Priority to registered donors on the waiting list for postmortal organs? A critical look at the objections. Journal of Medical Ethics 37: 149–152.</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR19">
<mixed-citation publication-type="other">den Hartogh, Govert (Forthcoming). Can consent be presumed?
<italic>Journal of Applied Philosophy.</italic>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR49">
<mixed-citation publication-type="other">den Hartogh, Govert (forthcoming 2). Tacitly consenting to donate one's organs. Journal of Medical Ethics.</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR20">
<mixed-citation publication-type="other">den Hartogh, Govert (Submitted). “In the best interests of the deceased”. A possible justification of organ removal without consent?</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR7">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>DuBois</surname>
<given-names>James M.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Increasing rates of organ donation: exploring the Institute of Medicine’s boldest recommendation</article-title>
<source>Journal of Clinical Ethics</source>
<year>2009</year>
<volume>20</volume>
<issue>1</issue>
<fpage>13</fpage>
<lpage>22</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">19385319</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR8">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Eaton</surname>
<given-names>S</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>The subtle politics of organ donation: A proposal</article-title>
<source>Journal of Medical Ethics</source>
<year>1998</year>
<volume>24</volume>
<fpage>166</fpage>
<lpage>170</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1136/jme.24.3.166</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">9650110</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR9">
<mixed-citation publication-type="book">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Engberts</surname>
<given-names>DP</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<source>Met recht en reden. Het gemeenschappelijke belang van medische ethiek en gezondheidsrecht</source>
<year>2005</year>
<publisher-loc>Leiden</publisher-loc>
<publisher-name>Inaugurele rede, Universiteit Leiden</publisher-name>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR11">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Etzioni</surname>
<given-names>Amitai</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Organ donation: A communitarian approach</article-title>
<source>Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal</source>
<year>2003</year>
<volume>13</volume>
<fpage>1</fpage>
<lpage>18</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1353/ken.2003.0004</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">12807104</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR12">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Farsides</surname>
<given-names>Tom</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Winning hearts and minds: Using psychology to promote voluntary organ donation</article-title>
<source>Health Care Analysis</source>
<year>2000</year>
<volume>8</volume>
<fpage>101</fpage>
<lpage>121</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1023/A:1009402628830</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">11183441</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR13">
<mixed-citation publication-type="book">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Feinberg</surname>
<given-names>Joel</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<source>Offense to others</source>
<year>1985</year>
<publisher-loc>New York</publisher-loc>
<publisher-name>Oxford University Press</publisher-name>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR14">
<mixed-citation publication-type="book">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Friele</surname>
<given-names>RD</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Kerssens</surname>
<given-names>JJ</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<source>Actieve donorregistratie? Een onderzoek naar de mogelijke reacties op de introductie van een actieve donorregistratie</source>
<year>2004</year>
<publisher-loc>Utrecht</publisher-loc>
<publisher-name>NIVEL</publisher-name>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR15">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Gevers</surname>
<given-names>S</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Janssen</surname>
<given-names>A</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Friele</surname>
<given-names>R</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Consent systems for post mortem organ donation in Europe</article-title>
<source>European Journal of Health Law</source>
<year>2004</year>
<volume>11</volume>
<issue>2</issue>
<fpage>175</fpage>
<lpage>186</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1163/1571809041457422</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">15387424</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR16">
<mixed-citation publication-type="book">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Godbout</surname>
<given-names>Jacques T</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Caillé</surname>
<given-names>Alain</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<source>L’Esprit du Don</source>
<year>1992</year>
<publisher-loc>Paris</publisher-loc>
<publisher-name>la Découverte</publisher-name>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR21">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Hilhorst</surname>
<given-names>Medard</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Directed altruistic living organ donation: Partial but not unfair</article-title>
<source>Ethical Theory and Moral Practice</source>
<year>2005</year>
<volume>8</volume>
<fpage>197</fpage>
<lpage>215</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1007/s10677-005-3295-3</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">16459404</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR26">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Jacob</surname>
<given-names>Marie</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Another look at the presumed-versus-informed consent dichotomy in postmortem organ procurement</article-title>
<source>Bioethics</source>
<year>2006</year>
<volume>20</volume>
<fpage>293</fpage>
<lpage>300</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1111/j.1467-8519.2006.00507.x</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR22">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Klassen</surname>
<given-names>AC</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Klassen</surname>
<given-names>DK</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Who are the donors in organ donation? The family’s perspective in mandated choice</article-title>
<source>Annals of Internal Medicine</source>
<year>1996</year>
<volume>125</volume>
<fpage>70</fpage>
<lpage>73</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">8644991</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR23">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Lauritzen</surname>
<given-names>Paul</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>McClure</surname>
<given-names>Michael</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Smith</surname>
<given-names>Martin L</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Trew</surname>
<given-names>Andrew</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>The gift of life and the common good</article-title>
<source>Hastings Center Report</source>
<year>2001</year>
<volume>31</volume>
<fpage>29</fpage>
<lpage>35</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">11478091</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR24">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Mackenzie</surname>
<given-names>Catriona</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Relational autonomy, normative authority and perfectionism</article-title>
<source>Journal of Social Philosophy</source>
<year>2008</year>
<volume>39</volume>
<fpage>512</fpage>
<lpage>533</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1111/j.1467-9833.2008.00440.x</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR25">
<mixed-citation publication-type="other">Mackenzie, Catriona, and Natalie Stoljar. (2000). Introduction to:
<italic>Relational autonomy, feminist perspectives on autonomy, agency and the social self</italic>
. Catriona Mackenzie, Natalie Stoljar, eds., New York: Oxford University Press.</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR27">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>May</surname>
<given-names>Thomas</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Aulisio</surname>
<given-names>Marc P</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Vita</surname>
<given-names>Michael A</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Patients, family, and organ donation: Who should decide?</article-title>
<source>The Milbank Quarterly</source>
<year>2000</year>
<volume>78</volume>
<fpage>323</fpage>
<lpage>336</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1111/1468-0009.00172</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">10934996</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR28">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Mongoven</surname>
<given-names>Ann</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Sharing our body and blood: organ donation and feminist critiques of sacrifice</article-title>
<source>Journal of Medicine and Philosophy</source>
<year>2003</year>
<volume>28</volume>
<fpage>89</fpage>
<lpage>114</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1076/jmep.28.1.89.14175</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">12715283</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR29">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Morris</surname>
<given-names>ED</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>The organ trail: Express vs presumed consent as paths to blaze in solving a critical shortage</article-title>
<source>Kentucky Law Journal</source>
<year>2002</year>
<volume>90</volume>
<fpage>1125</fpage>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR10">
<mixed-citation publication-type="book">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Nationaler </surname>
<given-names>Ethikrat</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<source>Increasing the number of organ donations: A pressing issue for transplant medicine in Germany</source>
<year>2007</year>
<publisher-loc>Berlin</publisher-loc>
<publisher-name>Nationaler Ethikrat</publisher-name>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR30">
<mixed-citation publication-type="book">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Nowenstein</surname>
<given-names>Graciela</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<person-group person-group-type="editor">
<name>
<surname>Garwood-Gowers</surname>
<given-names>Austen</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Tingle</surname>
<given-names>John</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Wheat</surname>
<given-names>Kay</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Nemo censetur ignorare legem? Presumed consent to organ donation in France, from Parliament to hospitals</article-title>
<source>Contemporary issues in healthcare law and ethics</source>
<year>2005</year>
<publisher-loc>Butterworth Heineman</publisher-loc>
<publisher-name>Oxford</publisher-name>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR31">
<mixed-citation publication-type="book">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Nowenstein</surname>
<given-names>Graciela</given-names>
</name>
<etal></etal>
</person-group>
<person-group person-group-type="editor">
<name>
<surname>Weimar</surname>
<given-names>Willem</given-names>
</name>
<etal></etal>
</person-group>
<article-title>Is presumed consent legislation just black letter law? Methodological and theoretical lessons from the French case</article-title>
<source>Organ transplantation—Ethical,legal and psychosocial aspects</source>
<year>2008</year>
<publisher-loc>Lengerich</publisher-loc>
<publisher-name>Pabst Science Publishers</publisher-name>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR32">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Radeck</surname>
<given-names>CM</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Jaccard</surname>
<given-names>J</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Psychological aspects of organ donation: a critical review and synthesis of individual and next-of-kin donation decisions</article-title>
<source>Health Psychology</source>
<year>1997</year>
<volume>16</volume>
<issue>2</issue>
<fpage>183</fpage>
<lpage>195</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1037/0278-6133.16.2.183</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">9269891</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR33">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Sanner</surname>
<given-names>Margaret A</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Two perspectives on organ donation: Experiences of potential donor families and intensive care physicians of the same event</article-title>
<source>Journal of Critical Care</source>
<year>2007</year>
<volume>22</volume>
<fpage>296</fpage>
<lpage>304</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1016/j.jcrc.2007.03.002</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">18086400</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR34">
<mixed-citation publication-type="book">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Schenderling</surname>
<given-names>J</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<person-group person-group-type="editor">
<name>
<surname>Boer</surname>
<given-names>T</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Roothaan</surname>
<given-names>A</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Schipperen met het eigen leven: Zelfsturing als normatief ideaal</article-title>
<source>Gegeven: Ethische essays over het leven als gave</source>
<year>2003</year>
<publisher-loc>Zoetermeer</publisher-loc>
<publisher-name>Uitgeverij Boekencentrum</publisher-name>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR35">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Siminoff</surname>
<given-names>Laura A</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Chillag</surname>
<given-names>Kata</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>The Fallacy of the ‘Gift of Life’</article-title>
<source>Hastings Center Report</source>
<year>1999</year>
<volume>29</volume>
<issue>6</issue>
<fpage>34</fpage>
<lpage>41</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.2307/3527870</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">10641243</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR36">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Siminoff</surname>
<given-names>Laura A</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Mercer</surname>
<given-names>Mary Beth</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Graham</surname>
<given-names>Gregory</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Burant</surname>
<given-names>Christopher</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>The reasons families donate organs for transplantation: implications for policy and practice</article-title>
<source>Journal of Trauma</source>
<year>2007</year>
<volume>62</volume>
<fpage>969</fpage>
<lpage>978</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1097/01.ta.0000205220.24003.51</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">17426556</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR37">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Spital</surname>
<given-names>Aron</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Mandated choice for organ donation: Time to give it a try</article-title>
<source>Annals of Internal Medicine</source>
<year>1996</year>
<volume>125</volume>
<fpage>66</fpage>
<lpage>69</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">8644990</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR38">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Sque</surname>
<given-names>Margaret RG</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Payne</surname>
<given-names>Sheila A</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Dissonant loss: the experiences of donor relatives</article-title>
<source>Social Science and Medicine</source>
<year>1996</year>
<volume>46</volume>
<fpage>1359</fpage>
<lpage>1370</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">8913005</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR39">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Sque</surname>
<given-names>Magi</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Long</surname>
<given-names>Tracy</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Payne</surname>
<given-names>Sheila</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Allardyce</surname>
<given-names>Diana</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Why relatives do not donate organs</article-title>
<source>Journal of Advanced Nursing</source>
<year>2008</year>
<volume>61</volume>
<issue>2</issue>
<fpage>134</fpage>
<lpage>144</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1111/j.1365-2648.2007.04491.x</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">18186905</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR40">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Streat</surname>
<given-names>Stephen</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Clinical review: Moral assumptions and the process of organ donation in the intensive care unit</article-title>
<source>Critical Care</source>
<year>2004</year>
<volume>8</volume>
<fpage>382</fpage>
<lpage>388</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1186/cc2876</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">15469581</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR41">
<mixed-citation publication-type="other">Taels, M., W.F. van Raaij. 2008.
<italic>Beslissystemen, beloningen en orgaandonatie</italic>
. Eindrapport in opdracht van het Ministerie van VWS,
<ext-link ext-link-type="uri" xlink:href="http://parlis.nl/pdf/bijlagen/BLG16260.pdf">http://parlis.nl/pdf/bijlagen/BLG16260.pdf</ext-link>
.</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR42">
<mixed-citation publication-type="book">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Veatch</surname>
<given-names>Robert M</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<source>Transplantation ethics</source>
<year>2000</year>
<publisher-loc>Washington D.C.</publisher-loc>
<publisher-name>Georgetown University Press</publisher-name>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR43">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Verheyde</surname>
<given-names>JL</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Rady</surname>
<given-names>MY</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Mc Gregor</surname>
<given-names>J</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Presumed Consent for organpreservation in uncontrolled donation after cartdiac death in the United States: a public policy with serious consequences</article-title>
<source>Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine</source>
<year>2009</year>
<volume>4</volume>
<fpage>15</fpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1186/1747-5341-4-15</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR44">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Wall</surname>
<given-names>Stephen P</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Dubler</surname>
<given-names>Nancy N</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Goldfrank</surname>
<given-names>Lewis R</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Translating the IOM’s “boldest recommendation” into accepted practice</article-title>
<source>Journal of Clinical Ethics</source>
<year>2009</year>
<volume>20</volume>
<issue>1</issue>
<fpage>23</fpage>
<lpage>28</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">19385320</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR45">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Wendler</surname>
<given-names>Dave</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Dickert</surname>
<given-names>Neil</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>The consent process for cadaveric organ procurement</article-title>
<source>JAMA</source>
<year>2001</year>
<volume>285</volume>
<issue>3</issue>
<fpage>329</fpage>
<lpage>334</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1001/jama.285.3.329</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">11176844</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR46">
<mixed-citation publication-type="book">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Wertheimer</surname>
<given-names>Alan</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<source>Consent to sexual relations</source>
<year>2003</year>
<publisher-loc>Cambridge</publisher-loc>
<publisher-name>Cambridge University Press</publisher-name>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="CR47">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Wilkinson</surname>
<given-names>T Martin</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Individual and family decisions about organ donation</article-title>
<source>Journal of Applied Philosophy</source>
<year>2007</year>
<volume>24</volume>
<issue>1</issue>
<fpage>26</fpage>
<lpage>40</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1111/j.1468-5930.2007.00339.x</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
</ref-list>
<fn-group>
<fn id="Fn1">
<label>1</label>
<p>Japanese law requires the consent of the donor for declaring him dead at the moment of brain-death, and hence for the removal of his organs. Lebanese law requires the consent of both the deceased and his relatives.</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn2">
<label>2</label>
<p>It is legally recognized in most countries with an opt-out system, but, for example, not in Austria and Italy. For France and Spain see note 11.</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn3">
<label>3</label>
<p>As some authors suggest, e.g. Gevers et al. (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR15">2004</xref>
).</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn4">
<label>4</label>
<p>As he says, the right to bodily integrity is one of our basic rights because we are embodied beings, but my dead body is no longer the embodiment of ‘me’. He also rightly points out that a right to bodily integrity would not rule out the overruling by the family of a decision to donate, because it is only a negative right.</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn5">
<label>5</label>
<p>Many opponents of ‘presumed consent’ see hardly any difference with conscription, e.g. Veatch (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR42">2000</xref>
), Etzioni (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR11">2003</xref>
), Bell (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR2">2006</xref>
), and Godbout and Caillé (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR16">1992</xref>
).</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn6">
<label>6</label>
<p>I have argued there that there are decisive differences between this case and taking organ removal as our default. I will draw upon that argument in Sect. "
<xref rid="Sec4" ref-type="sec">Donation by procuration?</xref>
", but do not presuppose its validity.</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn7">
<label>7</label>
<p>See note 1. It is also worth noting that in opt-in countries it is either legally allowed (UK) or common practice (the Netherlands) not to request consent for the following procedures: to go on with artificial respiration until brain death sets in, even if this does not serve any interest of the dying patient himself, and to take steps for preserving the organs, in particular in the case of potential non-heart beating donors (see Bell
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR2">2006</xref>
). Such steps are also taken without prior consent in the programmes, recently introduced in the USA, for retrieving organs from people who have suddenly died from cardiac arrest outside the hospital (Dubois
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR7">2009</xref>
). In the description Wall et al. (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR44">2009</xref>
) give of this procedure it is justified in terms of presumed consent. Requesting consent in the few minutes before ischemic damage occurs is often not feasible, and if it is feasible, many family refusals would probably occur. But if these considerations justify proceeding without actual consent, why is such consent required for taking out the organs? Cf. Verheyde et al. (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR43">2009</xref>
).</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn8">
<label>8</label>
<p>It may be possible for them, however, to meet the burden of proof, for evidence may be available showing that most people who didn’t register a decision themselves, will be happy to have the decision made by their relatives. For the Netherlands see Taels and van Raaij (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR41">2008</xref>
).</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn9">
<label>9</label>
<p>Veatch (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR42">2000</xref>
, p. 161) recognizes that decision by the next of kin is problematic from the point of view of the right of self-determination, but not that it is precisely as problematic as presumed consent and for the very same reason.</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn10">
<label>10</label>
<p>That has often been reported to be the public’s general view of the proper role of the relatives (Farsides
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR12">2000</xref>
, with further references). In the German transplantation law of 1997 it is explicitly stipulated that this is the task of the relatives; they have to be asked whether the deceased made any relevant statement during his life, and if not what they presume his will to have been. In France and Spain the law prescribes to ask the relatives for confirmation of the consent of the deceased, though in practice they are asked to consent themselves (Nowenstein
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR31">2008</xref>
). Actually, although for most relatives their view of the preferences of the deceased is the most important consideration, it is not always the only or decisive one—far from it (Farsides
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR12">2000</xref>
. Siminoff et al.
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR36">2007</xref>
; Sque and Payne
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR38">1996</xref>
; Sque et al.
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR39">2008</xref>
).</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn11">
<label>11</label>
<p>According to Sque et al. (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR39">2008</xref>
) a similar ambivalence between general pro-donation views and (in particular) concerns about the wholeness of the dead body characterizes many relatives.</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn12">
<label>12</label>
<p>The next of kin also have the right to demand an autopsy. However, there are considerable differences between this decision and a decision on donation, which makes it difficult to regard this as a precedent. For instance, for lack of relevant information the deceased is unable to take any binding decisions on an autopsy before his death, not even in the form of a veto. In the case of autopsy, therefore, there is every reason to assign the task of representing the deceased’s interests to the next of kin after his death.</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn13">
<label>13</label>
<p>According to Radeck and Jaccard (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR32">1997</xref>
) perceived support of the medical staff is a pivotal factor in consent decisions, cf. Siminoff et al. (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR36">2007</xref>
).</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn14">
<label>14</label>
<p>If the relatives cannot agree among themselves, taking out will also be refused, and the same happens when the burden of decision making is too much for the relatives under the circumstances.</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn15">
<label>15</label>
<p>This important argument is rarely found in the literature. It is briefly outlined by Engberts (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR9">2005</xref>
).</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn16">
<label>16</label>
<p>This should not be interpreted as criticism of utilitarianism in general; utilitarians are able to acknowledge the importance of special relationships and make allowances for them.</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn17">
<label>17</label>
<p>More needs to be said to establish that duty, cf. den Hartogh (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR48">2011</xref>
), with further references.</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn18">
<label>18</label>
<p>In the Netherlands only 40% of the population concur with the proposal not to ask for the consent of the next of kin if the deceased is a registered donor. (Friele and Kerssens
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR14">2004</xref>
, 18) The Dutch Organ Donation Act nevertheless has an explicit provision of this kind since 2006. Most American states have similar laws, as well as Canada, Australia and Switzerland, and of opt-out countries Belgium. But as a matter of fact in none of these countries a persistent refusal by the family to go along with the registered decision of the deceased to donate will be overruled, and such refusals regularly occur, in the Netherlands in 8% of the cases. In the USA only 12% of the OPO’s will in such a case overrule the refusal of the family (Wendler and Dickert
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR45">2001</xref>
).</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn19">
<label>19</label>
<p>Her argument is that patients are supported by the institutional power of the hospitals, but this is by no means automatically the case. In many cases it is the task of the intensivists who were responsible for the care of the deceased to ask the next of kin to consent to donation, and they tend to identify with the relatives, not with the organ recipients, see Sect. "
<xref rid="Sec7" ref-type="sec">Donation by procuration?</xref>
"</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn20">
<label>20</label>
<p>Which is one good reason why he should not be the person who opens the issue of donation with the family. Streat’s (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR40">2004</xref>
) plea in favour of the family’s right makes this perfectly clear by showing how an intensivist experiences the situation: the person who registered as a donor is dead, potential organ recipients are far away and he is confronted with the family and their grief. Cf. Nowenstein (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR30">2005</xref>
, 180–182) about the attitudes of French doctors.</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn21">
<label>21</label>
<p>According to research by Sque et al. (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR39">2008</xref>
) and Siminoff et al. (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR36">2007</xref>
973), resp. 41 and 44% of the next of kin decide to refuse consent to donation because the circumstances have already put such a strain on them that they are unable seriously to consider the request for consent. It is hard to reconcile this finding with the statement of Sque et al. that being asked for donation does not create an additional burden for the family.</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn22">
<label>22</label>
<p>See the characteristically fine discussion in Feinberg (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR13">1985</xref>
, 72–75). For the prohibition other reasons are often provided, e.g. the possibility of exploitation or resulting inequalities of access, but such effects can be prevented by institutional arrangements. That the sale of organs is seen as degrading seems to me the reason most basically motivating the opposition to it, perhaps in addition to the idea that the profit motive would crowd out altruistic motives.</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn23">
<label>23</label>
<p>See den Hartogh (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR17">2002</xref>
, pp. 67–71) for a criticism along these lines of the consent theory of political obligation. If these limitations on our options can be justified by other considerations without requiring consent, why is consent necessary?</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn24">
<label>24</label>
<p>A system like this is at present being discussed both in Germany and in the Netherlands. See Nationaler Ethikrat (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR10">2007</xref>
); Coördinatiegroep Orgaandonatie (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR6">2008</xref>
).</p>
</fn>
<fn id="Fn25">
<label>25</label>
<p>It is open to discussion whether or not we should retain in that system the option to register as a donor explicitly. This only makes sense if the law does not allow the relatives to overrule that decision. The effect might be that some of the people who now decide to register will not do so anymore, and in those cases the number of family refusals may be increased. But this may be more than compensated by the decreased number of family refusals in the case no registration had been made. See den Hartogh (
<xref ref-type="bibr" rid="CR18">2008</xref>
, pp. 102–106).</p>
</fn>
</fn-group>
</back>
</pmc>
</record>

Pour manipuler ce document sous Unix (Dilib)

EXPLOR_STEP=$WICRI_ROOT/Wicri/Belgique/explor/OpenAccessBelV2/Data/Pmc/Corpus
HfdSelect -h $EXPLOR_STEP/biblio.hfd -nk 000167 | SxmlIndent | more

Ou

HfdSelect -h $EXPLOR_AREA/Data/Pmc/Corpus/biblio.hfd -nk 000167 | SxmlIndent | more

Pour mettre un lien sur cette page dans le réseau Wicri

{{Explor lien
   |wiki=    Wicri/Belgique
   |area=    OpenAccessBelV2
   |flux=    Pmc
   |étape=   Corpus
   |type=    RBID
   |clé=     PMC:3319896
   |texte=   The role of the relatives in opt-in systems of postmortal organ procurement
}}

Pour générer des pages wiki

HfdIndexSelect -h $EXPLOR_AREA/Data/Pmc/Corpus/RBID.i   -Sk "pubmed:21365351" \
       | HfdSelect -Kh $EXPLOR_AREA/Data/Pmc/Corpus/biblio.hfd   \
       | NlmPubMed2Wicri -a OpenAccessBelV2 

Wicri

This area was generated with Dilib version V0.6.25.
Data generation: Thu Dec 1 00:43:49 2016. Site generation: Wed Mar 6 14:51:30 2024