Serveur d'exploration sur le patient édenté

Attention, ce site est en cours de développement !
Attention, site généré par des moyens informatiques à partir de corpus bruts.
Les informations ne sont donc pas validées.

Personal Inviolability and "Private Law"

Identifieur interne : 004D61 ( Istex/Corpus ); précédent : 004D60; suivant : 004D62

Personal Inviolability and "Private Law"

Auteurs : Gregory C. Keating

Source :

RBID : ISTEX:9B11A989F3874E66D04493162ACE695C7F74884D

English descriptors

Abstract

The “idea of private law” has occupied a prominent place in tort theorizing over the past twenty years. To American ears, the idea has a libertarian ring, implying a realm of private freedom beyond the reach of public power. But the idea of “private law” pursued in recent tort theory is different. This strand of tort theory takes an essentially formal view of “private law” as a form of adjudication through which one member of civil society invokes the public power of the state to call another member of civil society to account for breach of an obligation, owed by the latter to the former. In a number of recent, elegant essays, Arthur Ripstein has advanced a particular version of this view, a version distinguished in important part by its enlistment of the political philosophy of John Rawls in support of this project. Tort Law in a Liberal State is a further contribution to this project, summarizing Professor Ripstein’s view and arguing for both the interpretive and the philosophical plausibility of his project.Personal Inviolability and Private Law raises objections to both aspects of Ripstein’s project, and briefly explains why “public law” conceptions of tort are at least as plausible as “private law” ones, both philosophically and interpretively. Interpretively, Professor Ripstein’s conception is open to three serious objections. First, by placing the calling of one member of civil society to account by another at the center of their view, “private law” theorists threaten to place the remedial cart before the substantive horse. Prior to the late nineteenth century, tort existed—to the extent that it existed at all—as an essentially remedial body of law. Our modern law of torts comes into existence with (and by the recognition of) tort as a freestanding law of primary obligation. By placing such great weight both on Kant’s property-centered account of private law and on “private law” theory’s heavily remedial conception of tort, Professor Ripstein’s conception cuts against the fundamental thrust of modern tort law. That thrust is to make obligation central and to treat right and remedy as separable. Ripstein, by contrast, places enormous weight on remedy and takes right and remedy to be indivisible.Second, Tort Law in a Liberal State is, in important part, a brief for the fault principle. Professor Ripstein is right to distinguish between “harm-based” torts such as liability for accidental injury, negligently inflicted and right-based” torts such as trespass, but wrong to claim that “harm-based” liability in tort is always fault-based. This claim leads Professor Ripstein both to a distorted account of tort law’s various strict liabilities and to a fundamental mischaracterization of much of the conduct subject to liability in tort. Professor Ripstein’s recasting of strict liabilities as fault ones commits him to the unfortunate idea that there is something intrinsically wrong with valuable, productive activities, blamelessly conducted. Both the recasting of particular strict liabilities in fault terms, and the righteous condemnation of risk to which this recasting leads, are mistaken. Rylands conduct in the famous case of Rylands v. Fletcher was not wrongful; Atlantic Cement’s conduct in Boomer was not wrongful; and Lake Erie’s conduct in Vincent was not wrongful. In all of these cases, defendant’s only “fault” lay in (unreasonably) failing to make reparation for harm (reasonably) inflicted. More generally and more importantly, risk, like pollution, is not wrongful in itself, and harm is a matter of moral concern even when it issues from blameless conduct. Strict liability is a morally significant and instructive form of liability because it registers the perception that serious harm must sometimes be repaired, even though it has been faultlessly inflicted.Third and last, it is an interpretive mistake to insist that “public” and “private” forms of tort and accident law express fundamentally different values and moral conceptions. “Public law” schemes frequently complement or perfect “private law” ones, and threads of political morality tie private and public accident law institutions together. Zoning law’s relation to nuisance is only one of many cases in point.Professor Ripstein’s philosophical claims are likewise open to objection. For starters, Professor Ripstein’s attachment to the form of “private law” transforms Kant’s preoccupation with the inviolability of persons into a preoccupation with the formal purity of legal institutions. This is a path to avoid. An accident law faithful to the power of Kant’s philosophy must be give pride of place to the inviolability of our persons, not to the inviolability of our legal forms. That latter path leads to endowing legal rules with the intrinsic value held only by persons. Second, Ripstein’s assertion that Rawls’ theory of justice commits him to the particular institutional form of “private law” is unpersuasive. Famously and explicitly, Rawls’ theory leaves open the choice between capitalism and market socialism. The most natural and plausible reading of his theory of justice shows that it also leaves open the far more modest institutional choice between “private” and “public” law institutions.The final part of Personal Inviolability and “Private Law” briefly suggests that some form of enterprise liability constructed around a conception of commutative justice may, in fact, express the independence, equality and inviolability of democratic citizens more adequately than a “private law” constructed around a conception of corrective justice does. Free and equal citizens have ample reason not to place their rights against one another at the mercy of a “private law” negligence lottery, and to seek surer reparation for serious injury.

Url:
DOI: 10.2202/1932-9148.1048

Links to Exploration step

ISTEX:9B11A989F3874E66D04493162ACE695C7F74884D

Le document en format XML

<record>
<TEI wicri:istexFullTextTei="biblStruct">
<teiHeader>
<fileDesc>
<titleStmt>
<title xml:lang="en">Personal Inviolability and "Private Law"</title>
<author wicri:is="90%">
<name sortKey="Keating, Gregory C" sort="Keating, Gregory C" uniqKey="Keating G" first="Gregory C." last="Keating">Gregory C. Keating</name>
<affiliation>
<mods:affiliation>1University of Southern California, gkeating@law.usc.edu</mods:affiliation>
</affiliation>
<affiliation>
<mods:affiliation>University of Southern California, gkeating@law.usc.edu</mods:affiliation>
</affiliation>
<affiliation>
<mods:affiliation>E-mail: gkeating@law.usc.edu</mods:affiliation>
</affiliation>
</author>
</titleStmt>
<publicationStmt>
<idno type="wicri:source">ISTEX</idno>
<idno type="RBID">ISTEX:9B11A989F3874E66D04493162ACE695C7F74884D</idno>
<date when="2011" year="2011">2011</date>
<idno type="doi">10.2202/1932-9148.1048</idno>
<idno type="url">https://api.istex.fr/document/9B11A989F3874E66D04493162ACE695C7F74884D/fulltext/pdf</idno>
<idno type="wicri:Area/Istex/Corpus">004D61</idno>
<idno type="wicri:explorRef" wicri:stream="Istex" wicri:step="Corpus" wicri:corpus="ISTEX">004D61</idno>
</publicationStmt>
<sourceDesc>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<title level="a" type="main" xml:lang="en">Personal Inviolability and "Private Law"</title>
<author wicri:is="90%">
<name sortKey="Keating, Gregory C" sort="Keating, Gregory C" uniqKey="Keating G" first="Gregory C." last="Keating">Gregory C. Keating</name>
<affiliation>
<mods:affiliation>1University of Southern California, gkeating@law.usc.edu</mods:affiliation>
</affiliation>
<affiliation>
<mods:affiliation>University of Southern California, gkeating@law.usc.edu</mods:affiliation>
</affiliation>
<affiliation>
<mods:affiliation>E-mail: gkeating@law.usc.edu</mods:affiliation>
</affiliation>
</author>
</analytic>
<monogr></monogr>
<series>
<title level="j">Journal of Tort Law</title>
<idno type="eISSN">1932-9148</idno>
<imprint>
<publisher>De Gruyter</publisher>
<date type="published" when="2007-06-01">2007-06-01</date>
<biblScope unit="volume">1</biblScope>
<biblScope unit="issue">2</biblScope>
</imprint>
</series>
</biblStruct>
</sourceDesc>
</fileDesc>
<profileDesc>
<textClass>
<keywords scheme="KwdEn" xml:lang="en">
<term>Accident costs</term>
<term>Accidental harm</term>
<term>Accidental injury</term>
<term>Arthur ripstein</term>
<term>Boomer</term>
<term>Characteristic risks</term>
<term>Civil society</term>
<term>Commutative</term>
<term>Commutative justice</term>
<term>Conduct subject</term>
<term>Corrective</term>
<term>Corrective justice</term>
<term>Devastating injury</term>
<term>Economic analysis</term>
<term>Enterprise liability</term>
<term>Equal citizens</term>
<term>Equal persons</term>
<term>Ernest weinrib</term>
<term>Fairer</term>
<term>Fault liability</term>
<term>Good reason</term>
<term>Guido calabresi</term>
<term>Harm principle</term>
<term>Immediate relation</term>
<term>Injunction</term>
<term>Injurers</term>
<term>Inviolability</term>
<term>Jeremy waldron</term>
<term>John rawls</term>
<term>Keating</term>
<term>Keeton</term>
<term>Legislative stage</term>
<term>Liability</term>
<term>Liability insurance</term>
<term>Liberal state</term>
<term>Lottery</term>
<term>Modern nuisance</term>
<term>Negligence</term>
<term>Negligence liability</term>
<term>Nonfault</term>
<term>Nonfault liability</term>
<term>Nuisance</term>
<term>Ordinary negligence</term>
<term>Original position</term>
<term>Personal inviolability</term>
<term>Personal property</term>
<term>Physical harm</term>
<term>Physical integrity</term>
<term>Political authority</term>
<term>Political philosophy</term>
<term>Potential injurers</term>
<term>Precept</term>
<term>Private order</term>
<term>Private right</term>
<term>Professor ripstein</term>
<term>Property right</term>
<term>Public justice</term>
<term>Rawls</term>
<term>Rawlsian fairness</term>
<term>Remedial</term>
<term>Remedial conception</term>
<term>Reparation</term>
<term>Ripstein</term>
<term>Risk imposition</term>
<term>Risk impositions</term>
<term>Rylands</term>
<term>Similar risks</term>
<term>Social world</term>
<term>Strict liability</term>
<term>Theorist</term>
<term>Tort</term>
<term>Trespass</term>
<term>Waldron</term>
<term>Weinrib</term>
<term>Wrongful</term>
<term>Wrongful conduct</term>
</keywords>
<keywords scheme="Teeft" xml:lang="en">
<term>Accident costs</term>
<term>Accidental harm</term>
<term>Accidental injury</term>
<term>Arthur ripstein</term>
<term>Boomer</term>
<term>Characteristic risks</term>
<term>Civil society</term>
<term>Commutative</term>
<term>Commutative justice</term>
<term>Conduct subject</term>
<term>Corrective</term>
<term>Corrective justice</term>
<term>Devastating injury</term>
<term>Economic analysis</term>
<term>Enterprise liability</term>
<term>Equal citizens</term>
<term>Equal persons</term>
<term>Ernest weinrib</term>
<term>Fairer</term>
<term>Fault liability</term>
<term>Good reason</term>
<term>Guido calabresi</term>
<term>Harm principle</term>
<term>Immediate relation</term>
<term>Injunction</term>
<term>Injurers</term>
<term>Inviolability</term>
<term>Jeremy waldron</term>
<term>John rawls</term>
<term>Keating</term>
<term>Keeton</term>
<term>Legislative stage</term>
<term>Liability</term>
<term>Liability insurance</term>
<term>Liberal state</term>
<term>Lottery</term>
<term>Modern nuisance</term>
<term>Negligence</term>
<term>Negligence liability</term>
<term>Nonfault</term>
<term>Nonfault liability</term>
<term>Nuisance</term>
<term>Ordinary negligence</term>
<term>Original position</term>
<term>Personal inviolability</term>
<term>Personal property</term>
<term>Physical harm</term>
<term>Physical integrity</term>
<term>Political authority</term>
<term>Political philosophy</term>
<term>Potential injurers</term>
<term>Precept</term>
<term>Private order</term>
<term>Private right</term>
<term>Professor ripstein</term>
<term>Property right</term>
<term>Public justice</term>
<term>Rawls</term>
<term>Rawlsian fairness</term>
<term>Remedial</term>
<term>Remedial conception</term>
<term>Reparation</term>
<term>Ripstein</term>
<term>Risk imposition</term>
<term>Risk impositions</term>
<term>Rylands</term>
<term>Similar risks</term>
<term>Social world</term>
<term>Strict liability</term>
<term>Theorist</term>
<term>Tort</term>
<term>Trespass</term>
<term>Waldron</term>
<term>Weinrib</term>
<term>Wrongful</term>
<term>Wrongful conduct</term>
</keywords>
</textClass>
<langUsage>
<language ident="en">en</language>
</langUsage>
</profileDesc>
</teiHeader>
<front>
<div type="abstract" xml:lang="en">The “idea of private law” has occupied a prominent place in tort theorizing over the past twenty years. To American ears, the idea has a libertarian ring, implying a realm of private freedom beyond the reach of public power. But the idea of “private law” pursued in recent tort theory is different. This strand of tort theory takes an essentially formal view of “private law” as a form of adjudication through which one member of civil society invokes the public power of the state to call another member of civil society to account for breach of an obligation, owed by the latter to the former. In a number of recent, elegant essays, Arthur Ripstein has advanced a particular version of this view, a version distinguished in important part by its enlistment of the political philosophy of John Rawls in support of this project. Tort Law in a Liberal State is a further contribution to this project, summarizing Professor Ripstein’s view and arguing for both the interpretive and the philosophical plausibility of his project.Personal Inviolability and Private Law raises objections to both aspects of Ripstein’s project, and briefly explains why “public law” conceptions of tort are at least as plausible as “private law” ones, both philosophically and interpretively. Interpretively, Professor Ripstein’s conception is open to three serious objections. First, by placing the calling of one member of civil society to account by another at the center of their view, “private law” theorists threaten to place the remedial cart before the substantive horse. Prior to the late nineteenth century, tort existed—to the extent that it existed at all—as an essentially remedial body of law. Our modern law of torts comes into existence with (and by the recognition of) tort as a freestanding law of primary obligation. By placing such great weight both on Kant’s property-centered account of private law and on “private law” theory’s heavily remedial conception of tort, Professor Ripstein’s conception cuts against the fundamental thrust of modern tort law. That thrust is to make obligation central and to treat right and remedy as separable. Ripstein, by contrast, places enormous weight on remedy and takes right and remedy to be indivisible.Second, Tort Law in a Liberal State is, in important part, a brief for the fault principle. Professor Ripstein is right to distinguish between “harm-based” torts such as liability for accidental injury, negligently inflicted and right-based” torts such as trespass, but wrong to claim that “harm-based” liability in tort is always fault-based. This claim leads Professor Ripstein both to a distorted account of tort law’s various strict liabilities and to a fundamental mischaracterization of much of the conduct subject to liability in tort. Professor Ripstein’s recasting of strict liabilities as fault ones commits him to the unfortunate idea that there is something intrinsically wrong with valuable, productive activities, blamelessly conducted. Both the recasting of particular strict liabilities in fault terms, and the righteous condemnation of risk to which this recasting leads, are mistaken. Rylands conduct in the famous case of Rylands v. Fletcher was not wrongful; Atlantic Cement’s conduct in Boomer was not wrongful; and Lake Erie’s conduct in Vincent was not wrongful. In all of these cases, defendant’s only “fault” lay in (unreasonably) failing to make reparation for harm (reasonably) inflicted. More generally and more importantly, risk, like pollution, is not wrongful in itself, and harm is a matter of moral concern even when it issues from blameless conduct. Strict liability is a morally significant and instructive form of liability because it registers the perception that serious harm must sometimes be repaired, even though it has been faultlessly inflicted.Third and last, it is an interpretive mistake to insist that “public” and “private” forms of tort and accident law express fundamentally different values and moral conceptions. “Public law” schemes frequently complement or perfect “private law” ones, and threads of political morality tie private and public accident law institutions together. Zoning law’s relation to nuisance is only one of many cases in point.Professor Ripstein’s philosophical claims are likewise open to objection. For starters, Professor Ripstein’s attachment to the form of “private law” transforms Kant’s preoccupation with the inviolability of persons into a preoccupation with the formal purity of legal institutions. This is a path to avoid. An accident law faithful to the power of Kant’s philosophy must be give pride of place to the inviolability of our persons, not to the inviolability of our legal forms. That latter path leads to endowing legal rules with the intrinsic value held only by persons. Second, Ripstein’s assertion that Rawls’ theory of justice commits him to the particular institutional form of “private law” is unpersuasive. Famously and explicitly, Rawls’ theory leaves open the choice between capitalism and market socialism. The most natural and plausible reading of his theory of justice shows that it also leaves open the far more modest institutional choice between “private” and “public” law institutions.The final part of Personal Inviolability and “Private Law” briefly suggests that some form of enterprise liability constructed around a conception of commutative justice may, in fact, express the independence, equality and inviolability of democratic citizens more adequately than a “private law” constructed around a conception of corrective justice does. Free and equal citizens have ample reason not to place their rights against one another at the mercy of a “private law” negligence lottery, and to seek surer reparation for serious injury.</div>
</front>
</TEI>
<istex>
<corpusName>degruyter-journals</corpusName>
<keywords>
<teeft>
<json:string>tort</json:string>
<json:string>enterprise liability</json:string>
<json:string>ripstein</json:string>
<json:string>strict liability</json:string>
<json:string>negligence liability</json:string>
<json:string>corrective</json:string>
<json:string>rawls</json:string>
<json:string>personal inviolability</json:string>
<json:string>injurers</json:string>
<json:string>corrective justice</json:string>
<json:string>weinrib</json:string>
<json:string>inviolability</json:string>
<json:string>rylands</json:string>
<json:string>liability</json:string>
<json:string>keating</json:string>
<json:string>boomer</json:string>
<json:string>waldron</json:string>
<json:string>commutative</json:string>
<json:string>professor ripstein</json:string>
<json:string>original position</json:string>
<json:string>negligence</json:string>
<json:string>fault liability</json:string>
<json:string>accident costs</json:string>
<json:string>nonfault</json:string>
<json:string>equal persons</json:string>
<json:string>trespass</json:string>
<json:string>reparation</json:string>
<json:string>civil society</json:string>
<json:string>characteristic risks</json:string>
<json:string>wrongful</json:string>
<json:string>political philosophy</json:string>
<json:string>accidental injury</json:string>
<json:string>john rawls</json:string>
<json:string>commutative justice</json:string>
<json:string>lottery</json:string>
<json:string>keeton</json:string>
<json:string>ernest weinrib</json:string>
<json:string>physical harm</json:string>
<json:string>theorist</json:string>
<json:string>fairer</json:string>
<json:string>precept</json:string>
<json:string>private order</json:string>
<json:string>harm principle</json:string>
<json:string>political authority</json:string>
<json:string>devastating injury</json:string>
<json:string>social world</json:string>
<json:string>potential injurers</json:string>
<json:string>personal property</json:string>
<json:string>risk impositions</json:string>
<json:string>liberal state</json:string>
<json:string>guido calabresi</json:string>
<json:string>remedial conception</json:string>
<json:string>arthur ripstein</json:string>
<json:string>public justice</json:string>
<json:string>similar risks</json:string>
<json:string>accidental harm</json:string>
<json:string>jeremy waldron</json:string>
<json:string>wrongful conduct</json:string>
<json:string>legislative stage</json:string>
<json:string>remedial</json:string>
<json:string>nuisance</json:string>
<json:string>physical integrity</json:string>
<json:string>modern nuisance</json:string>
<json:string>private right</json:string>
<json:string>good reason</json:string>
<json:string>rawlsian fairness</json:string>
<json:string>risk imposition</json:string>
<json:string>property right</json:string>
<json:string>immediate relation</json:string>
<json:string>conduct subject</json:string>
<json:string>equal citizens</json:string>
<json:string>nonfault liability</json:string>
<json:string>liability insurance</json:string>
<json:string>ordinary negligence</json:string>
<json:string>economic analysis</json:string>
<json:string>injunction</json:string>
<json:string>precondition</json:string>
<json:string>george fletcher</json:string>
<json:string>devastating losses</json:string>
<json:string>tort theory</json:string>
<json:string>characteristic risk</json:string>
<json:string>libertarian idea</json:string>
<json:string>robert nozick</json:string>
<json:string>important part</json:string>
<json:string>potential victims</json:string>
<json:string>lives answer</json:string>
<json:string>devastating liability</json:string>
<json:string>direct regulation</json:string>
<json:string>harmful costs</json:string>
<json:string>individual actors</json:string>
<json:string>vicarious liability</json:string>
<json:string>rylands conduct</json:string>
<json:string>tort liability</json:string>
<json:string>interpersonal comparison</json:string>
<json:string>lake erie</json:string>
<json:string>famous case</json:string>
<json:string>psychological integrity</json:string>
<json:string>intrinsic value</json:string>
<json:string>market socialism</json:string>
<json:string>remedy clause</json:string>
<json:string>economic interests</json:string>
<json:string>cement plant</json:string>
<json:string>private rights</json:string>
<json:string>regime choice</json:string>
<json:string>obvious reason</json:string>
<json:string>equal freedom</json:string>
<json:string>undue hardship</json:string>
<json:string>irreparable injury</json:string>
<json:string>modern american nuisance</json:string>
<json:string>relevant risks</json:string>
<json:string>negligent</json:string>
<json:string>strict</json:string>
<json:string>imposition</json:string>
<json:string>damages</json:string>
<json:string>kant</json:string>
<json:string>infliction</json:string>
<json:string>community advantage</json:string>
<json:string>tortious wrongs</json:string>
<json:string>awards money damages</json:string>
<json:string>legitimate activities</json:string>
<json:string>money damages</json:string>
<json:string>salient fact</json:string>
<json:string>negligent conduct</json:string>
<json:string>property rights</json:string>
<json:string>diverse ways</json:string>
<json:string>liability rules</json:string>
<json:string>moral theory</json:string>
<json:string>such cases</json:string>
<json:string>institutional mechanism</json:string>
<json:string>harmful fallout</json:string>
<json:string>substantive question</json:string>
<json:string>private lawsuit</json:string>
<json:string>diverse ends</json:string>
<json:string>general idea</json:string>
<json:string>harmless trespasses</json:string>
<json:string>lottery ticket</json:string>
<json:string>conclusive presumptions</json:string>
<json:string>moral character</json:string>
<json:string>private purposes</json:string>
<json:string>institutional mechanisms</json:string>
<json:string>particular conception</json:string>
<json:string>intentional interference</json:string>
<json:string>accurate reading</json:string>
<json:string>emotional interests</json:string>
<json:string>intentional infliction</json:string>
<json:string>emotional distress</json:string>
<json:string>special responsibility</json:string>
<json:string>democratic citizens</json:string>
<json:string>theory risks</json:string>
<json:string>general domain</json:string>
<json:string>such harm</json:string>
<json:string>particular defendant</json:string>
<json:string>reasonable risk</json:string>
<json:string>legal institutions</json:string>
<json:string>legal positivism</json:string>
<json:string>political morality</json:string>
<json:string>serious harm</json:string>
<json:string>individual acts</json:string>
<json:string>fair terms</json:string>
<json:string>significant risks</json:string>
<json:string>instrumental policies</json:string>
<json:string>accident prevention</json:string>
<json:string>joel feinberg</json:string>
<json:string>large quantities</json:string>
<json:string>collective conception</json:string>
<json:string>institutional agency</json:string>
<json:string>faulty conduct</json:string>
<json:string>civil liability</json:string>
<json:string>commutative principle</json:string>
<json:string>accidental injuries</json:string>
<json:string>particular torts</json:string>
<json:string>universal laws</json:string>
<json:string>more weight</json:string>
<json:string>ripstein coleman</json:string>
<json:string>productive activities</json:string>
<json:string>favorable terms</json:string>
<json:string>automobile accidents</json:string>
<json:string>private agreement</json:string>
<json:string>devastating loss</json:string>
<json:string>insurance premiums</json:string>
<json:string>strict liabilities</json:string>
<json:string>private property</json:string>
<json:string>substantial measure</json:string>
<json:string>modern repudiation</json:string>
<json:string>massive loss</json:string>
<json:string>different kinds</json:string>
<json:string>automobile insurance</json:string>
<json:string>kantian justice</json:string>
<json:string>high level</json:string>
<json:string>liability regimes</json:string>
<json:string>robert keeton</json:string>
<json:string>modern tort</json:string>
<json:string>dangerous activities</json:string>
<json:string>professor conception</json:string>
<json:string>social worlds</json:string>
<json:string>ungeneralized wrongs</json:string>
<json:string>natural persons</json:string>
<json:string>small firms</json:string>
<json:string>coke bottles</json:string>
<json:string>tractor trailers</json:string>
<json:string>pure type</json:string>
<json:string>reasonable agreement</json:string>
<json:string>fairness case</json:string>
<json:string>nineteenth century</json:string>
<json:string>coast guard</json:string>
<json:string>particular idea</json:string>
<json:string>benjamin zipursky</json:string>
<json:string>momentary lapses</json:string>
<json:string>public power</json:string>
<json:string>southern california</json:string>
<json:string>retributive principle</json:string>
<json:string>civil recourse</json:string>
<json:string>such accidents</json:string>
<json:string>individual fault</json:string>
<json:string>particular parties</json:string>
<json:string>salient relation</json:string>
<json:string>traditional tort liability</json:string>
<json:string>natural misfortune</json:string>
<json:string>short step</json:string>
<json:string>fundamental interest</json:string>
<json:string>fairness</json:string>
<json:string>wrongdoing</json:string>
</teeft>
</keywords>
<author>
<json:item>
<name>Gregory C. Keating</name>
<affiliations>
<json:string>1University of Southern California, gkeating@law.usc.edu</json:string>
<json:string>University of Southern California, gkeating@law.usc.edu</json:string>
<json:string>E-mail: gkeating@law.usc.edu</json:string>
</affiliations>
</json:item>
</author>
<articleId>
<json:string>1932-9148.1048</json:string>
</articleId>
<arkIstex>ark:/67375/QT4-SHTH7XFX-X</arkIstex>
<language>
<json:string>eng</json:string>
</language>
<originalGenre>
<json:string>research-article</json:string>
</originalGenre>
<abstract>The “idea of private law” has occupied a prominent place in tort theorizing over the past twenty years. To American ears, the idea has a libertarian ring, implying a realm of private freedom beyond the reach of public power. But the idea of “private law” pursued in recent tort theory is different. This strand of tort theory takes an essentially formal view of “private law” as a form of adjudication through which one member of civil society invokes the public power of the state to call another member of civil society to account for breach of an obligation, owed by the latter to the former. In a number of recent, elegant essays, Arthur Ripstein has advanced a particular version of this view, a version distinguished in important part by its enlistment of the political philosophy of John Rawls in support of this project. Tort Law in a Liberal State is a further contribution to this project, summarizing Professor Ripstein’s view and arguing for both the interpretive and the philosophical plausibility of his project.Personal Inviolability and Private Law raises objections to both aspects of Ripstein’s project, and briefly explains why “public law” conceptions of tort are at least as plausible as “private law” ones, both philosophically and interpretively. Interpretively, Professor Ripstein’s conception is open to three serious objections. First, by placing the calling of one member of civil society to account by another at the center of their view, “private law” theorists threaten to place the remedial cart before the substantive horse. Prior to the late nineteenth century, tort existed—to the extent that it existed at all—as an essentially remedial body of law. Our modern law of torts comes into existence with (and by the recognition of) tort as a freestanding law of primary obligation. By placing such great weight both on Kant’s property-centered account of private law and on “private law” theory’s heavily remedial conception of tort, Professor Ripstein’s conception cuts against the fundamental thrust of modern tort law. That thrust is to make obligation central and to treat right and remedy as separable. Ripstein, by contrast, places enormous weight on remedy and takes right and remedy to be indivisible.Second, Tort Law in a Liberal State is, in important part, a brief for the fault principle. Professor Ripstein is right to distinguish between “harm-based” torts such as liability for accidental injury, negligently inflicted and right-based” torts such as trespass, but wrong to claim that “harm-based” liability in tort is always fault-based. This claim leads Professor Ripstein both to a distorted account of tort law’s various strict liabilities and to a fundamental mischaracterization of much of the conduct subject to liability in tort. Professor Ripstein’s recasting of strict liabilities as fault ones commits him to the unfortunate idea that there is something intrinsically wrong with valuable, productive activities, blamelessly conducted. Both the recasting of particular strict liabilities in fault terms, and the righteous condemnation of risk to which this recasting leads, are mistaken. Rylands conduct in the famous case of Rylands v. Fletcher was not wrongful; Atlantic Cement’s conduct in Boomer was not wrongful; and Lake Erie’s conduct in Vincent was not wrongful. In all of these cases, defendant’s only “fault” lay in (unreasonably) failing to make reparation for harm (reasonably) inflicted. More generally and more importantly, risk, like pollution, is not wrongful in itself, and harm is a matter of moral concern even when it issues from blameless conduct. Strict liability is a morally significant and instructive form of liability because it registers the perception that serious harm must sometimes be repaired, even though it has been faultlessly inflicted.Third and last, it is an interpretive mistake to insist that “public” and “private” forms of tort and accident law express fundamentally different values and moral conceptions. “Public law” schemes frequently complement or perfect “private law” ones, and threads of political morality tie private and public accident law institutions together. Zoning law’s relation to nuisance is only one of many cases in point.Professor Ripstein’s philosophical claims are likewise open to objection. For starters, Professor Ripstein’s attachment to the form of “private law” transforms Kant’s preoccupation with the inviolability of persons into a preoccupation with the formal purity of legal institutions. This is a path to avoid. An accident law faithful to the power of Kant’s philosophy must be give pride of place to the inviolability of our persons, not to the inviolability of our legal forms. That latter path leads to endowing legal rules with the intrinsic value held only by persons. Second, Ripstein’s assertion that Rawls’ theory of justice commits him to the particular institutional form of “private law” is unpersuasive. Famously and explicitly, Rawls’ theory leaves open the choice between capitalism and market socialism. The most natural and plausible reading of his theory of justice shows that it also leaves open the far more modest institutional choice between “private” and “public” law institutions.The final part of Personal Inviolability and “Private Law” briefly suggests that some form of enterprise liability constructed around a conception of commutative justice may, in fact, express the independence, equality and inviolability of democratic citizens more adequately than a “private law” constructed around a conception of corrective justice does. Free and equal citizens have ample reason not to place their rights against one another at the mercy of a “private law” negligence lottery, and to seek surer reparation for serious injury.</abstract>
<qualityIndicators>
<score>10</score>
<pdfWordCount>20882</pdfWordCount>
<pdfCharCount>119777</pdfCharCount>
<pdfVersion>1.4</pdfVersion>
<pdfPageCount>44</pdfPageCount>
<pdfPageSize>612 x 792 pts (letter)</pdfPageSize>
<refBibsNative>false</refBibsNative>
<abstractWordCount>894</abstractWordCount>
<abstractCharCount>5785</abstractCharCount>
<keywordCount>0</keywordCount>
</qualityIndicators>
<title>Personal Inviolability and "Private Law"</title>
<genre>
<json:string>research-article</json:string>
</genre>
<host>
<title>Journal of Tort Law</title>
<language>
<json:string>unknown</json:string>
</language>
<eissn>
<json:string>1932-9148</json:string>
</eissn>
<publisherId>
<json:string>jtl</json:string>
</publisherId>
<volume>1</volume>
<issue>2</issue>
<genre>
<json:string>journal</json:string>
</genre>
<subject>
<json:item>
<value>tort law</value>
</json:item>
</subject>
</host>
<namedEntities>
<unitex>
<date>
<json:string>2007-06-01</json:string>
<json:string>twentieth century</json:string>
<json:string>in the Nineteenth Century</json:string>
<json:string>nineteenth century</json:string>
<json:string>1910</json:string>
<json:string>1897</json:string>
</date>
<geogName></geogName>
<orgName>
<json:string>Del Webb Development Co.</json:string>
<json:string>South Buffalo Railway Co.</json:string>
<json:string>New Zealand Accident Compensation Act</json:string>
<json:string>Lake Erie Transportation Co.</json:string>
<json:string>Little Joseph Realty, Inc</json:string>
<json:string>Institutional Agency</json:string>
<json:string>MODERN AMERICAN REMEDIES</json:string>
<json:string>Gresham Transfer, Inc.</json:string>
<json:string>United States Airlines, Inc</json:string>
<json:string>Atlantic Cement Co.</json:string>
<json:string>University of Virginia Law Review</json:string>
<json:string>Freeman Coal Mining Corp</json:string>
<json:string>Department of Transportation</json:string>
<json:string>American State Constitutions</json:string>
<json:string>University of Southern California</json:string>
<json:string>Effective Agency Rawls</json:string>
</orgName>
<orgName_funder></orgName_funder>
<orgName_provider></orgName_provider>
<persName>
<json:string>George Fletcher</json:string>
<json:string>A. Liberty</json:string>
<json:string>S. C. Ct</json:string>
<json:string>J. Postema</json:string>
<json:string>James A. Henderson</json:string>
<json:string>Christopher Schroeder</json:string>
<json:string>Fate</json:string>
<json:string>Jeremy Waldron</json:string>
<json:string>John Rawls</json:string>
<json:string>John Fabian</json:string>
<json:string>Boomer</json:string>
<json:string>See</json:string>
<json:string>Joel Feinberg</json:string>
<json:string>Henry Friendly</json:string>
<json:string>Hurt</json:string>
<json:string>Douglas Melamed</json:string>
<json:string>Barbara Herman</json:string>
<json:string>Richard Epstein</json:string>
<json:string>Arthur Ripstein</json:string>
<json:string>Stephen Perry</json:string>
<json:string>Jules Coleman</json:string>
<json:string>John Salmond</json:string>
<json:string>David Lewis</json:string>
<json:string>Security</json:string>
<json:string>John Gardner</json:string>
<json:string>Stuart Mill</json:string>
<json:string>F.Supp</json:string>
<json:string>In</json:string>
<json:string>Thomas C. Grey</json:string>
<json:string>Ripstein</json:string>
<json:string>Benjamin C. Zipursky</json:string>
<json:string>Cathy Sharkey</json:string>
<json:string>Oregon Constitution</json:string>
<json:string>Benjamin Zipursky</json:string>
<json:string>Robert Keeton</json:string>
<json:string>Robert Nozick</json:string>
<json:string>Samuel Isaacharoff</json:string>
<json:string>Ernest Weinrib</json:string>
<json:string>Jon T. Hirschoff</json:string>
<json:string>B. Enterprise</json:string>
<json:string>Scott Altman</json:string>
<json:string>A. Harm</json:string>
<json:string>Erin Garvey</json:string>
<json:string>Guido Calabresi</json:string>
<json:string>Oliver Wendell</json:string>
<json:string>L. Rev</json:string>
<json:string>Samuel Freeman</json:string>
<json:string>Richard A. Posner</json:string>
<json:string>Fault</json:string>
<json:string>Ben Zipursky</json:string>
<json:string>Holmes</json:string>
<json:string>Gregory C. Keating</json:string>
<json:string>Ira S. Bushey</json:string>
<json:string>Rawls</json:string>
<json:string>Clare Dalton</json:string>
<json:string>Weinrib</json:string>
<json:string>An Essay</json:string>
</persName>
<placeName>
<json:string>Iowa City</json:string>
<json:string>D.C.</json:string>
<json:string>United States</json:string>
<json:string>Lubin</json:string>
<json:string>Washington</json:string>
<json:string>American</json:string>
<json:string>TORONTO</json:string>
<json:string>New Zealand</json:string>
<json:string>York</json:string>
<json:string>Goldberg</json:string>
</placeName>
<ref_url></ref_url>
<ref_bibl>
<json:string>[1992]</json:string>
<json:string>[2007]</json:string>
<json:string>1954 [original publication date, 1920</json:string>
<json:string>Bernard Gagnebin et al.</json:string>
</ref_bibl>
<bibl></bibl>
</unitex>
</namedEntities>
<ark>
<json:string>ark:/67375/QT4-SHTH7XFX-X</json:string>
</ark>
<categories>
<inist>
<json:string>1 - sciences humaines et sociales</json:string>
</inist>
</categories>
<publicationDate>2007</publicationDate>
<copyrightDate>2011</copyrightDate>
<doi>
<json:string>10.2202/1932-9148.1048</json:string>
</doi>
<id>9B11A989F3874E66D04493162ACE695C7F74884D</id>
<score>1</score>
<fulltext>
<json:item>
<extension>pdf</extension>
<original>true</original>
<mimetype>application/pdf</mimetype>
<uri>https://api.istex.fr/document/9B11A989F3874E66D04493162ACE695C7F74884D/fulltext/pdf</uri>
</json:item>
<json:item>
<extension>zip</extension>
<original>false</original>
<mimetype>application/zip</mimetype>
<uri>https://api.istex.fr/document/9B11A989F3874E66D04493162ACE695C7F74884D/fulltext/zip</uri>
</json:item>
<istex:fulltextTEI uri="https://api.istex.fr/document/9B11A989F3874E66D04493162ACE695C7F74884D/fulltext/tei">
<teiHeader>
<fileDesc>
<titleStmt>
<title level="a" type="main" xml:lang="en">Personal Inviolability and "Private Law"</title>
<respStmt>
<resp>Références bibliographiques récupérées via GROBID</resp>
<name resp="ISTEX-API">ISTEX-API (INIST-CNRS)</name>
</respStmt>
</titleStmt>
<publicationStmt>
<authority>ISTEX</authority>
<publisher scheme="https://publisher-list.data.istex.fr">De Gruyter</publisher>
<availability>
<licence>
<p>©2011 Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co. KG, Berlin/Boston</p>
</licence>
<p scheme="https://loaded-corpus.data.istex.fr/ark:/67375/XBH-B4QPMMZB-D">degruyter-journals</p>
</availability>
<date>2007-06-01</date>
</publicationStmt>
<notesStmt>
<note type="research-article" scheme="https://content-type.data.istex.fr/ark:/67375/XTP-1JC4F85T-7">research-article</note>
<note type="journal" scheme="https://publication-type.data.istex.fr/ark:/67375/JMC-0GLKJH51-B">journal</note>
</notesStmt>
<sourceDesc>
<biblStruct type="inbook">
<analytic>
<title level="a" type="main" xml:lang="en">Personal Inviolability and "Private Law"</title>
<author xml:id="author-0000">
<persName>
<forename type="first">Gregory C.</forename>
<surname>Keating</surname>
</persName>
<email>gkeating@law.usc.edu</email>
<affiliation>1University of Southern California, gkeating@law.usc.edu</affiliation>
<affiliation>University of Southern California, gkeating@law.usc.edu</affiliation>
</author>
<idno type="istex">9B11A989F3874E66D04493162ACE695C7F74884D</idno>
<idno type="ark">ark:/67375/QT4-SHTH7XFX-X</idno>
<idno type="DOI">10.2202/1932-9148.1048</idno>
<idno type="article-id">1932-9148.1048</idno>
<idno type="pdf">jtl.2007.1.2.1048.pdf</idno>
</analytic>
<monogr>
<title level="j">Journal of Tort Law</title>
<idno type="eISSN">1932-9148</idno>
<idno type="publisher-id">jtl</idno>
<imprint>
<publisher>De Gruyter</publisher>
<date type="published" when="2007-06-01"></date>
<biblScope unit="volume">1</biblScope>
<biblScope unit="issue">2</biblScope>
</imprint>
</monogr>
</biblStruct>
</sourceDesc>
</fileDesc>
<profileDesc>
<creation>
<date>2007-06-01</date>
</creation>
<langUsage>
<language ident="en">en</language>
</langUsage>
<abstract xml:lang="en">
<p>The “idea of private law” has occupied a prominent place in tort theorizing over the past twenty years. To American ears, the idea has a libertarian ring, implying a realm of private freedom beyond the reach of public power. But the idea of “private law” pursued in recent tort theory is different. This strand of tort theory takes an essentially formal view of “private law” as a form of adjudication through which one member of civil society invokes the public power of the state to call another member of civil society to account for breach of an obligation, owed by the latter to the former. In a number of recent, elegant essays, Arthur Ripstein has advanced a particular version of this view, a version distinguished in important part by its enlistment of the political philosophy of John Rawls in support of this project. Tort Law in a Liberal State is a further contribution to this project, summarizing Professor Ripstein’s view and arguing for both the interpretive and the philosophical plausibility of his project.Personal Inviolability and Private Law raises objections to both aspects of Ripstein’s project, and briefly explains why “public law” conceptions of tort are at least as plausible as “private law” ones, both philosophically and interpretively. Interpretively, Professor Ripstein’s conception is open to three serious objections. First, by placing the calling of one member of civil society to account by another at the center of their view, “private law” theorists threaten to place the remedial cart before the substantive horse. Prior to the late nineteenth century, tort existed—to the extent that it existed at all—as an essentially remedial body of law. Our modern law of torts comes into existence with (and by the recognition of) tort as a freestanding law of primary obligation. By placing such great weight both on Kant’s property-centered account of private law and on “private law” theory’s heavily remedial conception of tort, Professor Ripstein’s conception cuts against the fundamental thrust of modern tort law. That thrust is to make obligation central and to treat right and remedy as separable. Ripstein, by contrast, places enormous weight on remedy and takes right and remedy to be indivisible.Second, Tort Law in a Liberal State is, in important part, a brief for the fault principle. Professor Ripstein is right to distinguish between “harm-based” torts such as liability for accidental injury, negligently inflicted and right-based” torts such as trespass, but wrong to claim that “harm-based” liability in tort is always fault-based. This claim leads Professor Ripstein both to a distorted account of tort law’s various strict liabilities and to a fundamental mischaracterization of much of the conduct subject to liability in tort. Professor Ripstein’s recasting of strict liabilities as fault ones commits him to the unfortunate idea that there is something intrinsically wrong with valuable, productive activities, blamelessly conducted. Both the recasting of particular strict liabilities in fault terms, and the righteous condemnation of risk to which this recasting leads, are mistaken. Rylands conduct in the famous case of Rylands v. Fletcher was not wrongful; Atlantic Cement’s conduct in Boomer was not wrongful; and Lake Erie’s conduct in Vincent was not wrongful. In all of these cases, defendant’s only “fault” lay in (unreasonably) failing to make reparation for harm (reasonably) inflicted. More generally and more importantly, risk, like pollution, is not wrongful in itself, and harm is a matter of moral concern even when it issues from blameless conduct. Strict liability is a morally significant and instructive form of liability because it registers the perception that serious harm must sometimes be repaired, even though it has been faultlessly inflicted.Third and last, it is an interpretive mistake to insist that “public” and “private” forms of tort and accident law express fundamentally different values and moral conceptions. “Public law” schemes frequently complement or perfect “private law” ones, and threads of political morality tie private and public accident law institutions together. Zoning law’s relation to nuisance is only one of many cases in point.Professor Ripstein’s philosophical claims are likewise open to objection. For starters, Professor Ripstein’s attachment to the form of “private law” transforms Kant’s preoccupation with the inviolability of persons into a preoccupation with the formal purity of legal institutions. This is a path to avoid. An accident law faithful to the power of Kant’s philosophy must be give pride of place to the inviolability of our persons, not to the inviolability of our legal forms. That latter path leads to endowing legal rules with the intrinsic value held only by persons. Second, Ripstein’s assertion that Rawls’ theory of justice commits him to the particular institutional form of “private law” is unpersuasive. Famously and explicitly, Rawls’ theory leaves open the choice between capitalism and market socialism. The most natural and plausible reading of his theory of justice shows that it also leaves open the far more modest institutional choice between “private” and “public” law institutions.The final part of Personal Inviolability and “Private Law” briefly suggests that some form of enterprise liability constructed around a conception of commutative justice may, in fact, express the independence, equality and inviolability of democratic citizens more adequately than a “private law” constructed around a conception of corrective justice does. Free and equal citizens have ample reason not to place their rights against one another at the mercy of a “private law” negligence lottery, and to seek surer reparation for serious injury.</p>
</abstract>
<textClass>
<keywords scheme="Journal Subject">
<list>
<head></head>
<item>
<term>tort law</term>
</item>
</list>
</keywords>
</textClass>
</profileDesc>
<revisionDesc>
<change when="2007-06-01">Created</change>
<change when="2007-06-01">Published</change>
<change xml:id="refBibs-istex" who="#ISTEX-API" when="2017-10-5">References added</change>
</revisionDesc>
</teiHeader>
</istex:fulltextTEI>
<json:item>
<extension>txt</extension>
<original>false</original>
<mimetype>text/plain</mimetype>
<uri>https://api.istex.fr/document/9B11A989F3874E66D04493162ACE695C7F74884D/fulltext/txt</uri>
</json:item>
</fulltext>
<metadata>
<istex:metadataXml wicri:clean="corpus degruyter-journals" wicri:toSee="no header">
<istex:xmlDeclaration>version="1.0" encoding="utf-8"</istex:xmlDeclaration>
<istex:docType PUBLIC="-//Atypon//DTD Atypon Systems Journal Archiving and Interchange NLM DTD v3.0.2 20101108//EN" URI="atypon_archive-interchange-dtd-3.0.2/atypon-archivearticle3.dtd" name="istex:docType"></istex:docType>
<istex:document>
<article article-type="research-article" dtd-version="3.0" xml:lang="EN">
<front>
<journal-meta>
<journal-id journal-id-type="publisher-id">jtl</journal-id>
<journal-title-group>
<journal-title>Journal of Tort Law</journal-title>
</journal-title-group>
<issn pub-type="epub">1932-9148</issn>
<publisher>
<publisher-name>De Gruyter</publisher-name>
</publisher>
</journal-meta>
<article-meta>
<article-id pub-id-type="publisher-id">1932-9148.1048</article-id>
<article-id pub-id-type="doi">10.2202/1932-9148.1048</article-id>
<article-categories>
<subj-group subj-group-type="heading">
<subject>Article</subject>
</subj-group>
<subj-group>
<subject>tort law</subject>
</subj-group>
</article-categories>
<title-group>
<article-title>Personal Inviolability and "Private Law"</article-title>
</title-group>
<contrib-group>
<contrib contrib-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Keating</surname>
<given-names>Gregory C.</given-names>
</name>
<xref ref-type="aff" rid="a1">
<sup>1</sup>
</xref>
<aff id="a1">
<sup>1</sup>
University of Southern California,
<email xlink:href="mailto:gkeating@law.usc.edu">gkeating@law.usc.edu</email>
</aff>
</contrib>
</contrib-group>
<pub-date pub-type="epub">
<day>1</day>
<month>6</month>
<year>2007</year>
</pub-date>
<volume>1</volume>
<issue>2</issue>
<permissions>
<copyright-statement>©2011 Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co. KG, Berlin/Boston</copyright-statement>
<copyright-year>2011</copyright-year>
</permissions>
<related-article related-article-type="pdf" xlink:href="jtl.2007.1.2.1048.pdf"></related-article>
<abstract>
<p>The “idea of private law” has occupied a prominent place in tort theorizing over the past twenty years. To American ears, the idea has a libertarian ring, implying a realm of private freedom beyond the reach of public power. But the idea of “private law” pursued in recent tort theory is different. This strand of tort theory takes an essentially formal view of “private law” as a form of adjudication through which one member of civil society invokes the public power of the state to call another member of civil society to account for breach of an obligation, owed by the latter to the former. In a number of recent, elegant essays, Arthur Ripstein has advanced a particular version of this view, a version distinguished in important part by its enlistment of the political philosophy of John Rawls in support of this project. Tort Law in a Liberal State is a further contribution to this project, summarizing Professor Ripstein’s view and arguing for both the interpretive and the philosophical plausibility of his project.Personal Inviolability and Private Law raises objections to both aspects of Ripstein’s project, and briefly explains why “public law” conceptions of tort are at least as plausible as “private law” ones, both philosophically and interpretively. Interpretively, Professor Ripstein’s conception is open to three serious objections. First, by placing the calling of one member of civil society to account by another at the center of their view, “private law” theorists threaten to place the remedial cart before the substantive horse. Prior to the late nineteenth century, tort existed—to the extent that it existed at all—as an essentially remedial body of law. Our modern law of torts comes into existence with (and by the recognition of) tort as a freestanding law of primary obligation. By placing such great weight both on Kant’s property-centered account of private law and on “private law” theory’s heavily remedial conception of tort, Professor Ripstein’s conception cuts against the fundamental thrust of modern tort law. That thrust is to make obligation central and to treat right and remedy as separable. Ripstein, by contrast, places enormous weight on remedy and takes right and remedy to be indivisible.Second, Tort Law in a Liberal State is, in important part, a brief for the fault principle. Professor Ripstein is right to distinguish between “harm-based” torts such as liability for accidental injury, negligently inflicted and right-based” torts such as trespass, but wrong to claim that “harm-based” liability in tort is always fault-based. This claim leads Professor Ripstein both to a distorted account of tort law’s various strict liabilities and to a fundamental mischaracterization of much of the conduct subject to liability in tort. Professor Ripstein’s recasting of strict liabilities as fault ones commits him to the unfortunate idea that there is something intrinsically wrong with valuable, productive activities, blamelessly conducted. Both the recasting of particular strict liabilities in fault terms, and the righteous condemnation of risk to which this recasting leads, are mistaken. Rylands conduct in the famous case of Rylands v. Fletcher was not wrongful; Atlantic Cement’s conduct in Boomer was not wrongful; and Lake Erie’s conduct in Vincent was not wrongful. In all of these cases, defendant’s only “fault” lay in (unreasonably) failing to make reparation for harm (reasonably) inflicted. More generally and more importantly, risk, like pollution, is not wrongful in itself, and harm is a matter of moral concern even when it issues from blameless conduct. Strict liability is a morally significant and instructive form of liability because it registers the perception that serious harm must sometimes be repaired, even though it has been faultlessly inflicted.Third and last, it is an interpretive mistake to insist that “public” and “private” forms of tort and accident law express fundamentally different values and moral conceptions. “Public law” schemes frequently complement or perfect “private law” ones, and threads of political morality tie private and public accident law institutions together. Zoning law’s relation to nuisance is only one of many cases in point.Professor Ripstein’s philosophical claims are likewise open to objection. For starters, Professor Ripstein’s attachment to the form of “private law” transforms Kant’s preoccupation with the inviolability of persons into a preoccupation with the formal purity of legal institutions. This is a path to avoid. An accident law faithful to the power of Kant’s philosophy must be give pride of place to the inviolability of our persons, not to the inviolability of our legal forms. That latter path leads to endowing legal rules with the intrinsic value held only by persons. Second, Ripstein’s assertion that Rawls’ theory of justice commits him to the particular institutional form of “private law” is unpersuasive. Famously and explicitly, Rawls’ theory leaves open the choice between capitalism and market socialism. The most natural and plausible reading of his theory of justice shows that it also leaves open the far more modest institutional choice between “private” and “public” law institutions.The final part of Personal Inviolability and “Private Law” briefly suggests that some form of enterprise liability constructed around a conception of commutative justice may, in fact, express the independence, equality and inviolability of democratic citizens more adequately than a “private law” constructed around a conception of corrective justice does. Free and equal citizens have ample reason not to place their rights against one another at the mercy of a “private law” negligence lottery, and to seek surer reparation for serious injury.</p>
</abstract>
<counts>
<page-count count="44"></page-count>
</counts>
</article-meta>
</front>
</article>
</istex:document>
</istex:metadataXml>
<mods version="3.6">
<titleInfo lang="en">
<title>Personal Inviolability and "Private Law"</title>
</titleInfo>
<titleInfo type="alternative" lang="en" contentType="CDATA">
<title>Personal Inviolability and "Private Law"</title>
</titleInfo>
<name type="personal">
<namePart type="given">Gregory C.</namePart>
<namePart type="family">Keating</namePart>
<affiliation>1University of Southern California, gkeating@law.usc.edu</affiliation>
<affiliation>University of Southern California, gkeating@law.usc.edu</affiliation>
<affiliation>E-mail: gkeating@law.usc.edu</affiliation>
</name>
<typeOfResource>text</typeOfResource>
<genre type="research-article" displayLabel="research-article" authority="ISTEX" authorityURI="https://content-type.data.istex.fr" valueURI="https://content-type.data.istex.fr/ark:/67375/XTP-1JC4F85T-7">research-article</genre>
<originInfo>
<publisher>De Gruyter</publisher>
<dateIssued encoding="w3cdtf">2007-06-01</dateIssued>
<dateCreated encoding="w3cdtf">2007-06-01</dateCreated>
<copyrightDate encoding="w3cdtf">2011</copyrightDate>
</originInfo>
<language>
<languageTerm type="code" authority="iso639-2b">eng</languageTerm>
<languageTerm type="code" authority="rfc3066">en</languageTerm>
</language>
<abstract lang="en">The “idea of private law” has occupied a prominent place in tort theorizing over the past twenty years. To American ears, the idea has a libertarian ring, implying a realm of private freedom beyond the reach of public power. But the idea of “private law” pursued in recent tort theory is different. This strand of tort theory takes an essentially formal view of “private law” as a form of adjudication through which one member of civil society invokes the public power of the state to call another member of civil society to account for breach of an obligation, owed by the latter to the former. In a number of recent, elegant essays, Arthur Ripstein has advanced a particular version of this view, a version distinguished in important part by its enlistment of the political philosophy of John Rawls in support of this project. Tort Law in a Liberal State is a further contribution to this project, summarizing Professor Ripstein’s view and arguing for both the interpretive and the philosophical plausibility of his project.Personal Inviolability and Private Law raises objections to both aspects of Ripstein’s project, and briefly explains why “public law” conceptions of tort are at least as plausible as “private law” ones, both philosophically and interpretively. Interpretively, Professor Ripstein’s conception is open to three serious objections. First, by placing the calling of one member of civil society to account by another at the center of their view, “private law” theorists threaten to place the remedial cart before the substantive horse. Prior to the late nineteenth century, tort existed—to the extent that it existed at all—as an essentially remedial body of law. Our modern law of torts comes into existence with (and by the recognition of) tort as a freestanding law of primary obligation. By placing such great weight both on Kant’s property-centered account of private law and on “private law” theory’s heavily remedial conception of tort, Professor Ripstein’s conception cuts against the fundamental thrust of modern tort law. That thrust is to make obligation central and to treat right and remedy as separable. Ripstein, by contrast, places enormous weight on remedy and takes right and remedy to be indivisible.Second, Tort Law in a Liberal State is, in important part, a brief for the fault principle. Professor Ripstein is right to distinguish between “harm-based” torts such as liability for accidental injury, negligently inflicted and right-based” torts such as trespass, but wrong to claim that “harm-based” liability in tort is always fault-based. This claim leads Professor Ripstein both to a distorted account of tort law’s various strict liabilities and to a fundamental mischaracterization of much of the conduct subject to liability in tort. Professor Ripstein’s recasting of strict liabilities as fault ones commits him to the unfortunate idea that there is something intrinsically wrong with valuable, productive activities, blamelessly conducted. Both the recasting of particular strict liabilities in fault terms, and the righteous condemnation of risk to which this recasting leads, are mistaken. Rylands conduct in the famous case of Rylands v. Fletcher was not wrongful; Atlantic Cement’s conduct in Boomer was not wrongful; and Lake Erie’s conduct in Vincent was not wrongful. In all of these cases, defendant’s only “fault” lay in (unreasonably) failing to make reparation for harm (reasonably) inflicted. More generally and more importantly, risk, like pollution, is not wrongful in itself, and harm is a matter of moral concern even when it issues from blameless conduct. Strict liability is a morally significant and instructive form of liability because it registers the perception that serious harm must sometimes be repaired, even though it has been faultlessly inflicted.Third and last, it is an interpretive mistake to insist that “public” and “private” forms of tort and accident law express fundamentally different values and moral conceptions. “Public law” schemes frequently complement or perfect “private law” ones, and threads of political morality tie private and public accident law institutions together. Zoning law’s relation to nuisance is only one of many cases in point.Professor Ripstein’s philosophical claims are likewise open to objection. For starters, Professor Ripstein’s attachment to the form of “private law” transforms Kant’s preoccupation with the inviolability of persons into a preoccupation with the formal purity of legal institutions. This is a path to avoid. An accident law faithful to the power of Kant’s philosophy must be give pride of place to the inviolability of our persons, not to the inviolability of our legal forms. That latter path leads to endowing legal rules with the intrinsic value held only by persons. Second, Ripstein’s assertion that Rawls’ theory of justice commits him to the particular institutional form of “private law” is unpersuasive. Famously and explicitly, Rawls’ theory leaves open the choice between capitalism and market socialism. The most natural and plausible reading of his theory of justice shows that it also leaves open the far more modest institutional choice between “private” and “public” law institutions.The final part of Personal Inviolability and “Private Law” briefly suggests that some form of enterprise liability constructed around a conception of commutative justice may, in fact, express the independence, equality and inviolability of democratic citizens more adequately than a “private law” constructed around a conception of corrective justice does. Free and equal citizens have ample reason not to place their rights against one another at the mercy of a “private law” negligence lottery, and to seek surer reparation for serious injury.</abstract>
<relatedItem type="host">
<titleInfo>
<title>Journal of Tort Law</title>
</titleInfo>
<genre type="journal" authority="ISTEX" authorityURI="https://publication-type.data.istex.fr" valueURI="https://publication-type.data.istex.fr/ark:/67375/JMC-0GLKJH51-B">journal</genre>
<originInfo></originInfo>
<subject>
<topic>tort law</topic>
</subject>
<identifier type="eISSN">1932-9148</identifier>
<identifier type="PublisherID">jtl</identifier>
<part>
<date>2007</date>
<detail type="volume">
<caption>vol.</caption>
<number>1</number>
</detail>
<detail type="issue">
<caption>no.</caption>
<number>2</number>
</detail>
<extent unit="pages">
<total>44</total>
</extent>
</part>
</relatedItem>
<identifier type="istex">9B11A989F3874E66D04493162ACE695C7F74884D</identifier>
<identifier type="ark">ark:/67375/QT4-SHTH7XFX-X</identifier>
<identifier type="DOI">10.2202/1932-9148.1048</identifier>
<identifier type="ArticleID">1932-9148.1048</identifier>
<identifier type="pdf">jtl.2007.1.2.1048.pdf</identifier>
<accessCondition type="use and reproduction" contentType="copyright">©2011 Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co. KG, Berlin/Boston</accessCondition>
<recordInfo>
<recordContentSource authority="ISTEX" authorityURI="https://loaded-corpus.data.istex.fr" valueURI="https://loaded-corpus.data.istex.fr/ark:/67375/XBH-B4QPMMZB-D">degruyter-journals</recordContentSource>
<recordOrigin>©2011 Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co. KG, Berlin/Boston</recordOrigin>
</recordInfo>
</mods>
<json:item>
<extension>json</extension>
<original>false</original>
<mimetype>application/json</mimetype>
<uri>https://api.istex.fr/document/9B11A989F3874E66D04493162ACE695C7F74884D/metadata/json</uri>
</json:item>
</metadata>
<serie></serie>
</istex>
</record>

Pour manipuler ce document sous Unix (Dilib)

EXPLOR_STEP=$WICRI_ROOT/Wicri/Santé/explor/EdenteV2/Data/Istex/Corpus
HfdSelect -h $EXPLOR_STEP/biblio.hfd -nk 004D61 | SxmlIndent | more

Ou

HfdSelect -h $EXPLOR_AREA/Data/Istex/Corpus/biblio.hfd -nk 004D61 | SxmlIndent | more

Pour mettre un lien sur cette page dans le réseau Wicri

{{Explor lien
   |wiki=    Wicri/Santé
   |area=    EdenteV2
   |flux=    Istex
   |étape=   Corpus
   |type=    RBID
   |clé=     ISTEX:9B11A989F3874E66D04493162ACE695C7F74884D
   |texte=   Personal Inviolability and "Private Law"
}}

Wicri

This area was generated with Dilib version V0.6.32.
Data generation: Thu Nov 30 15:26:48 2017. Site generation: Tue Mar 8 16:36:20 2022