Serveur d'exploration Xenakis

Attention, ce site est en cours de développement !
Attention, site généré par des moyens informatiques à partir de corpus bruts.
Les informations ne sont donc pas validées.

Musicology and Psychomusicology: Two Sciences of Music

Identifieur interne : 000329 ( Istex/Corpus ); précédent : 000328; suivant : 000330

Musicology and Psychomusicology: Two Sciences of Music

Auteurs : Otto E. Laske

Source :

RBID : ISTEX:2CE7E3C702658579B7A1D2507D1A5A930CDD374D

English descriptors


Url:
DOI: 10.1177/030573567752002

Links to Exploration step

ISTEX:2CE7E3C702658579B7A1D2507D1A5A930CDD374D

Le document en format XML

<record>
<TEI wicri:istexFullTextTei="biblStruct">
<teiHeader>
<fileDesc>
<titleStmt>
<title xml:lang="en">Musicology and Psychomusicology: Two Sciences of Music</title>
<author wicri:is="90%">
<name sortKey="Laske, Otto E" sort="Laske, Otto E" uniqKey="Laske O" first="Otto E." last="Laske">Otto E. Laske</name>
<affiliation>
<mods:affiliation>University of Illinois, Urbana, IL 61801, USA.</mods:affiliation>
</affiliation>
</author>
</titleStmt>
<publicationStmt>
<idno type="wicri:source">ISTEX</idno>
<idno type="RBID">ISTEX:2CE7E3C702658579B7A1D2507D1A5A930CDD374D</idno>
<date when="1977" year="1977">1977</date>
<idno type="doi">10.1177/030573567752002</idno>
<idno type="url">https://api.istex.fr/document/2CE7E3C702658579B7A1D2507D1A5A930CDD374D/fulltext/pdf</idno>
<idno type="wicri:Area/Istex/Corpus">000329</idno>
<idno type="wicri:explorRef" wicri:stream="Istex" wicri:step="Corpus" wicri:corpus="ISTEX">000329</idno>
</publicationStmt>
<sourceDesc>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<title level="a" type="main" xml:lang="en">Musicology and Psychomusicology: Two Sciences of Music</title>
<author wicri:is="90%">
<name sortKey="Laske, Otto E" sort="Laske, Otto E" uniqKey="Laske O" first="Otto E." last="Laske">Otto E. Laske</name>
<affiliation>
<mods:affiliation>University of Illinois, Urbana, IL 61801, USA.</mods:affiliation>
</affiliation>
</author>
</analytic>
<monogr></monogr>
<series>
<title level="j">Psychology of music</title>
<idno type="ISSN">0305-7356</idno>
<idno type="eISSN">1741-3087</idno>
<imprint>
<publisher>Sage Publications</publisher>
<pubPlace>Sage CA: Thousand Oaks, CA</pubPlace>
<date type="published" when="1977-10">1977-10</date>
<biblScope unit="volume">5</biblScope>
<biblScope unit="issue">2</biblScope>
<biblScope unit="page" from="10">10</biblScope>
<biblScope unit="page" to="22">22</biblScope>
</imprint>
<idno type="ISSN">0305-7356</idno>
</series>
</biblStruct>
</sourceDesc>
<seriesStmt>
<idno type="ISSN">0305-7356</idno>
</seriesStmt>
</fileDesc>
<profileDesc>
<textClass>
<keywords scheme="Teeft" xml:lang="en">
<term>Science collections</term>
</keywords>
</textClass>
<langUsage>
<language ident="en">en</language>
</langUsage>
</profileDesc>
</teiHeader>
</TEI>
<istex>
<corpusName>sage</corpusName>
<keywords>
<teeft>
<json:string>science collections</json:string>
</teeft>
</keywords>
<author>
<json:item>
<name>Otto E. Laske</name>
<affiliations>
<json:string>University of Illinois, Urbana, IL 61801, USA.</json:string>
</affiliations>
</json:item>
</author>
<articleId>
<json:string>10.1177_030573567752002</json:string>
</articleId>
<arkIstex>ark:/67375/M70-9KM9MZRZ-T</arkIstex>
<language>
<json:string>eng</json:string>
</language>
<originalGenre>
<json:string>research-article</json:string>
</originalGenre>
<qualityIndicators>
<score>2.021</score>
<pdfWordCount>9</pdfWordCount>
<pdfCharCount>54</pdfCharCount>
<pdfVersion>1.3</pdfVersion>
<pdfPageCount>13</pdfPageCount>
<pdfPageSize>382.68 x 623.64 pts</pdfPageSize>
<refBibsNative>true</refBibsNative>
<abstractWordCount>1</abstractWordCount>
<abstractCharCount>0</abstractCharCount>
<keywordCount>0</keywordCount>
</qualityIndicators>
<title>Musicology and Psychomusicology: Two Sciences of Music</title>
<genre>
<json:string>research-article</json:string>
</genre>
<host>
<title>Psychology of music</title>
<language>
<json:string>unknown</json:string>
</language>
<issn>
<json:string>0305-7356</json:string>
</issn>
<eissn>
<json:string>1741-3087</json:string>
</eissn>
<publisherId>
<json:string>POM</json:string>
</publisherId>
<volume>5</volume>
<issue>2</issue>
<pages>
<first>10</first>
<last>22</last>
</pages>
<genre>
<json:string>journal</json:string>
</genre>
</host>
<namedEntities>
<unitex>
<date>
<json:string>1977</json:string>
</date>
<geogName></geogName>
<orgName></orgName>
<orgName_funder></orgName_funder>
<orgName_provider></orgName_provider>
<persName></persName>
<placeName></placeName>
<ref_url></ref_url>
<ref_bibl></ref_bibl>
<bibl></bibl>
</unitex>
</namedEntities>
<ark>
<json:string>ark:/67375/M70-9KM9MZRZ-T</json:string>
</ark>
<categories>
<wos>
<json:string>1 - social science</json:string>
<json:string>2 - psychology, experimental</json:string>
<json:string>2 - psychology, educational</json:string>
<json:string>2 - psychology, applied</json:string>
</wos>
<scienceMetrix>
<json:string>1 - health sciences</json:string>
<json:string>2 - psychology & cognitive sciences</json:string>
<json:string>3 - experimental psychology</json:string>
</scienceMetrix>
<scopus>
<json:string>1 - Social Sciences</json:string>
<json:string>2 - Psychology</json:string>
<json:string>3 - Psychology (miscellaneous)</json:string>
<json:string>1 - Social Sciences</json:string>
<json:string>2 - Arts and Humanities</json:string>
<json:string>3 - Music</json:string>
</scopus>
</categories>
<publicationDate>1977</publicationDate>
<copyrightDate>1977</copyrightDate>
<doi>
<json:string>10.1177/030573567752002</json:string>
</doi>
<id>2CE7E3C702658579B7A1D2507D1A5A930CDD374D</id>
<score>1</score>
<fulltext>
<json:item>
<extension>pdf</extension>
<original>true</original>
<mimetype>application/pdf</mimetype>
<uri>https://api.istex.fr/document/2CE7E3C702658579B7A1D2507D1A5A930CDD374D/fulltext/pdf</uri>
</json:item>
<json:item>
<extension>ocr</extension>
<original>false</original>
<mimetype>text/ocr</mimetype>
<uri>https://api.istex.fr/document/2CE7E3C702658579B7A1D2507D1A5A930CDD374D/fulltext/ocr</uri>
</json:item>
<json:item>
<extension>zip</extension>
<original>false</original>
<mimetype>application/zip</mimetype>
<uri>https://api.istex.fr/document/2CE7E3C702658579B7A1D2507D1A5A930CDD374D/fulltext/zip</uri>
</json:item>
<istex:fulltextTEI uri="https://api.istex.fr/document/2CE7E3C702658579B7A1D2507D1A5A930CDD374D/fulltext/tei">
<teiHeader>
<fileDesc>
<titleStmt>
<title level="a" type="main" xml:lang="en">Musicology and Psychomusicology: Two Sciences of Music</title>
</titleStmt>
<publicationStmt>
<authority>ISTEX</authority>
<publisher scheme="https://publisher-list.data.istex.fr">Sage Publications</publisher>
<pubPlace>Sage CA: Thousand Oaks, CA</pubPlace>
<availability>
<licence>
<p>sage</p>
</licence>
</availability>
<p scheme="https://loaded-corpus.data.istex.fr/ark:/67375/XBH-0J1N7DQT-B"></p>
<date>1977</date>
</publicationStmt>
<notesStmt>
<note type="research-article" scheme="https://content-type.data.istex.fr/ark:/67375/XTP-1JC4F85T-7">research-article</note>
<note type="journal" scheme="https://publication-type.data.istex.fr/ark:/67375/JMC-0GLKJH51-B">journal</note>
</notesStmt>
<sourceDesc>
<biblStruct type="inbook">
<analytic>
<title level="a" type="main" xml:lang="en">Musicology and Psychomusicology: Two Sciences of Music</title>
<author xml:id="author-0000">
<persName>
<forename type="first">Otto E.</forename>
<surname>Laske</surname>
</persName>
<affiliation>University of Illinois, Urbana, IL 61801, USA.</affiliation>
</author>
<idno type="istex">2CE7E3C702658579B7A1D2507D1A5A930CDD374D</idno>
<idno type="ark">ark:/67375/M70-9KM9MZRZ-T</idno>
<idno type="DOI">10.1177/030573567752002</idno>
<idno type="article-id">10.1177_030573567752002</idno>
</analytic>
<monogr>
<title level="j">Psychology of music</title>
<idno type="pISSN">0305-7356</idno>
<idno type="eISSN">1741-3087</idno>
<idno type="publisher-id">POM</idno>
<idno type="PublisherID-hwp">sppom</idno>
<imprint>
<publisher>Sage Publications</publisher>
<pubPlace>Sage CA: Thousand Oaks, CA</pubPlace>
<date type="published" when="1977-10"></date>
<biblScope unit="volume">5</biblScope>
<biblScope unit="issue">2</biblScope>
<biblScope unit="page" from="10">10</biblScope>
<biblScope unit="page" to="22">22</biblScope>
</imprint>
</monogr>
</biblStruct>
</sourceDesc>
</fileDesc>
<profileDesc>
<creation>
<date>1977</date>
</creation>
<langUsage>
<language ident="en">en</language>
</langUsage>
</profileDesc>
<revisionDesc>
<change when="1977-10">Published</change>
</revisionDesc>
</teiHeader>
</istex:fulltextTEI>
<json:item>
<extension>txt</extension>
<original>false</original>
<mimetype>text/plain</mimetype>
<uri>https://api.istex.fr/document/2CE7E3C702658579B7A1D2507D1A5A930CDD374D/fulltext/txt</uri>
</json:item>
</fulltext>
<metadata>
<istex:metadataXml wicri:clean="corpus sage not found" wicri:toSee="no header">
<istex:xmlDeclaration>version="1.0" encoding="UTF-8"</istex:xmlDeclaration>
<istex:docType PUBLIC="-//NLM//DTD Journal Publishing DTD v2.3 20070202//EN" URI="journalpublishing.dtd" name="istex:docType"></istex:docType>
<istex:document>
<article article-type="research-article" dtd-version="2.3" xml:lang="EN">
<front>
<journal-meta>
<journal-id journal-id-type="hwp">sppom</journal-id>
<journal-id journal-id-type="publisher-id">POM</journal-id>
<journal-title>Psychology of Music</journal-title>
<issn pub-type="ppub">0305-7356</issn>
<publisher>
<publisher-name>Sage Publications</publisher-name>
<publisher-loc>Sage CA: Thousand Oaks, CA</publisher-loc>
</publisher>
</journal-meta>
<article-meta>
<article-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1177/030573567752002</article-id>
<article-id pub-id-type="publisher-id">10.1177_030573567752002</article-id>
<article-categories>
<subj-group subj-group-type="heading">
<subject>Articles</subject>
</subj-group>
</article-categories>
<title-group>
<article-title>Musicology and Psychomusicology: Two Sciences of Music</article-title>
</title-group>
<contrib-group>
<contrib contrib-type="author" xlink:type="simple">
<name name-style="western">
<surname>Laske</surname>
<given-names>Otto E.</given-names>
</name>
<aff>University of Illinois, Urbana, IL 61801, USA.</aff>
</contrib>
</contrib-group>
<pub-date pub-type="ppub">
<month>10</month>
<year>1977</year>
</pub-date>
<volume>5</volume>
<issue>2</issue>
<fpage>10</fpage>
<lpage>22</lpage>
<custom-meta-wrap>
<custom-meta xlink:type="simple">
<meta-name>sagemeta-type</meta-name>
<meta-value>Journal Article</meta-value>
</custom-meta>
<custom-meta xlink:type="simple">
<meta-name>search-text</meta-name>
<meta-value> MUSICOLOGY AND PSYCHOMUSICOLOGY: TWO SCIENCES OF MUSIC OTTO E. LASKE Abstract The distinction between structure and process in music is explored. Musicoiogy is defined as a science of musical structures represented in musical miemory It is shown that traditional music theory is syntax-centric and why, on account of that orientation, it has failed to raise many essential questions about musics Finally, the relationship between musicology and psychomusicology is defined, and some general conclusions concerning a theory of mtusical institoctiott arte drawn. In the present essay it is my intention to introduce a new scientific approacil to music, that of psychomusicology. I intend to outline the purpose and the scope of the new science, and link its viewpoint to that adopted by the established musical disciplines of musicology, music theory, and music analysis. I shall largely disregard the many technical distinctions between these three muisical disciplines and, instead, shall concentrate on what they share. In positive rather than critical terms, I shall discuss the reasons whv a procedural approach to music, as it is exemplified by psychomusicology, is needed. I shall elaborate upon the structure of a theory of music, and upon the link that binds the theors t instructional applications. I can conceive of many valid reasons for adopting the iine ol researchl allni thinking I am following in psychomusicological investigation. In particular, I adii motivated by a strong interest in the procedures employed in imiusical activiti. and their relationship to musical structures that result from them. A theoretical approach to music that pays primary attention to this relationship is best called "'procedural". To explain what I mean by this term, let me quote a few sentences by Jean Piaget (1964): "'To know an object is to act on it. To know is to modifsi to transform the object, and to understand the process of this transformation- and as a consequence, to understand the way the object is constructed." Indeed, as a composer living in the present rather than in the past of music, I am naturally interested in musical activities. However (and this makes my interest moi e epistemological than psychological), I am not interested in behavioui per se. buti rather in the lawful, systematic link of behaviouLr with te stiuctural jesuilts that it produces before my eyes and ears. As a composer, it has been my natural occupation for a long time to obsei vc musical activities. I have been profoundly astonished to find the process I observed, and the structure emerging from it, linked in many systematic (although not immediately obvious) ways. As a listener, when mapping out the set of a music's real or imaginary pasts in my memory, and as a music analyst, whlen making decisions about what the generative components of a musical structuie are, the same astonishment has overtaken me. External tokens of musical artifacts notwithstanding, such as notation, written analyses, tape recordings, and computer printouts, I came to the realisation that music is only what one is doing, "modifying and transforming the object and, as a consequence, understanding how the object is constructed". Going one step beyond my astonishment, I stipulated that there be a science of this interrelation of musical structure and The present essay is the basis of chapter one of Music, Menmory and Thought, Ann Arboi-. Michigan, USA: Xerox University Microfilms, 1977. It first appeared in In TheorY Onil YnTi Arbor Michigan, School of Music, University of Michigan (vol. 1. I - 12 t976) lil process, that could be called a theory of music. Finally, I searched for scientific means that were available for explicating the relationship between musical activities and their lawful structural results. Having found these means, I can now say that a procedural theory of music is possible, viable, teachable, and applicable to the learning and teaching of music. I I have implicitly defined a theory of music as a discipline that explicates the systematic relation linking activities called musical to their products, also called musical. Imagine now that the study of musical products, or artifacts, and the study of the mental processes that give rise to them are carried out by two separate disciplines: call the former "musicology", and the latter "psychomusicology". The theory of music is, then, a discipline whose task it is to link systematically what we know about music as an object or structure to what we know about music as an activity or process. Effecting this linkage is indeed what musicians are doing when they are engaged in listening to or making music. The scientific challenge lies in showing explicitly what the relationship is between the two aspects, or representations, of music. The fact that two different representations of one and the same music exist seems astonishing at first. But upon further thought, it becomes evident that this twofold representation music as product, and music as process-derives from a well-known phenomenon, viz. the dichotomy involved in all of human existence between perceiving the environment and acting upon it (Simon, 1962). Clearly, if there is any systematic link between musical activity and musical artefact, then it exists because both in perceiving and in acting upon our environment, we use essentially the same mental faculties. Musical man, as revealed in his works, is just a particularly striking example of this generative dichotomy. In linking the perceiving to the acting musician, a procedural theory of music pays homage to his undivided self. I have, so far, discussed the link between musical process and artefact with regard to possible connections between the two theories called musicology and psychomusicology. Let us now consider the phenomenon of the structure-process distinction in music more directly. Acting and perceiving are equally involved in all that humans do, and it is only if one proceeds to invent separate mental representations for their outcomes that their linkage becomes unclear. Over the centuries, musicians have found ingenious ways of objectifying what is perceived by ear. For instance, they represent musical objects graphically, by notation, or verbally, by calling them a structure; or else, they represent them on digital or analog tape and call them sounding. A comparable representation for musical action would require film or video tape, or some action notation. Even so, only the surface structure of the action would be elucidated. Obviously, then, one needs to employ some mechanism, or set of rules, to describe the action part of music satisfactorily. It is quite revealing that in his course of development (of which this century has seen important new stirrings) musical man has developed one piece of technology after another for linking musical perception to musical action and for establishing various kinds of feedback between them. The most important piece of technology yet developed is what is called a "compositional rule". Com- positional rules are also called "syntactic rules", viz. rules that specify how items can be put together under certain contextual conditions. We say, for instance, "it is a rule in (most of) sixteenth-century counterpoint that two simultaneously descending or ascending tones should not be at a distance of the interval of a fifth". I will not discuss here whether such a rule can be considered a music- *A music-grammatical rule claims universal validity within the scope of some musical tradition, whereas a stylistic rule is part of a set of rules defining a personal style. 11 grammatical rule, or whether it is better understood as a stylistic rule. [he lawful character of the rule will be preserved under either of these interpretations. It is more important to pay attention to what such a rule does: directly, with regard to musical action, the rule defines a procedure, or a subroutine, for linking sounds or layers of sound. However, it does so in a neutral way, without imposing any restrictions on the acoustic source or the semadntic relevance oi the sounds so linked. This neutrality is characteristic of syntactic i ules. One can say that, in terms of the structural side of music, the rule implicitly links two different representations, viz. a sonic (or, better, a sonological) and a semantic representation of music. The sonological representation of a music states how thc music sounds in terms of perceivable features; it is a scientific kind of solfege The semantic representation of a music states what the conceptual components are that make a music seem lawful, lawlike, or consistent with its own remete C3 recent past. A syntactic rule thus defines a link between the sound of a (perceived music and its sense or meaning; it has both a musicological (structural) and psychomusicological (procedural) significance. I can now make clear wxhai I meant by calling compositional rules an instance of nmusical technologyv 1I You may know of the question asked by Charles Ives in one of his LEss1i . Before a Sonata: "What does music have to do with souind?!" This questiols is usually taken to express a transcendentalist credo. Be that as it may, the ques- tion implies a relationship, although in a rhetorical, implicitly negative form One might equally well ask: "What does language have to do with speech ?'^ Is it a pure chance result of human evolution that language and music came to link up with sound for the purpose of conveying meaningful messages? That would be curious indeed. It is true, we do know of sign languages in whicl tihe auditory component has been replaced by a visual component (i.e. gestures)* and we know of people capable of reading music silently as one reads a book, and of people following the weird suggestions of musical notation in writing a triple canon. Nevertheless, most of us regard music as being intrinsically related to the occurrence of sound events. But what precisely does music have to do with sound? Or, to give a pragmatic twist to the question: lhow do miiusicians link sound and intellect? The answer to this question is simple or complex depending on whethel- one takes it to be an end in itself, or whether one explores the answer further. The answer is: musical man has a memory*. When pursuing the series of psychological questions that this metaphorical answer implies, one realises that man has whole battery of memories. Each of these memories has its own time constant (i.e. can hold information for different periods of time), and a different structure (i.e. holds different kinds of information, or the same information in different forms of internal representation). What, however, is a memory? It is a goal- oriented mechanism that: first, stores information; second, interprets information it receives; third, compares received information with what it already contains ot "knows"; and fourth, evaluates the truthfulness or consistency of what it receives in terms of past experience. Information stored in memory can take two different forms: that of procedures (or programmes), and that of data. More generally, memory comprises two equally important parts: a data base where the sttuff memory contains is stored, and the interpretive process that uses the information stored in the data base. The latter is the procedural component of memory, the former, the structural component (Lindsay, 1972; pp. 385-6). The previously made distinctions between structure and process on the one *For an excellent overview of the developmental literature, and for considerations of involuntai-y versus deliberate memory, see Brown (1975); for the close relationship of memory and intelligenc (musically speaking, semantics and syntax), see Piaget (1973), especially pp. 400-401t 12 hand, and sound and intellect on the other, now begin to take on manageable proportions. Although the two distinctions are in no way synonymous, they shall presently reveal their inherent relatedness. Of the two distinctions, that between structure and process is the overriding, more general one. It is a distinc- tion that can be maintained only outside of memory. Within memory, structure or data and process or program are intrinsically related and nearly indistinguish- able. They are two aspects of the workings of the central nervous system, in information-processing terms the central processor. One speaks of structure when one assumes the performing system to be at rest and objectifies the content it has processed so far. One speaks of process when one views the performing system as being in action and as working on some object or structure. This "acting upon, modifying, and transforming of" an object, according to Piaget, is knowledge. In music, the objects worked upon, modified, and transformed are "sound objects". There would be no way of relating sound objects to the human intellect, nor even conceiving of sound objects, if it were not for the fact that humans have a memory. The sensory buffers that receive acoustic information can hold that information for only minimal amounts of time. Even sensory images, produced in a preperceptual store within memory, last only up to 250 msec., or a quarter-second (Massaro, 1975; pp. 439ff). Therefore, linking sound to the intellect is really a matter of: first, storing sound in various memories until it reaches long-term memory (i.e. makes contact with past experience); and second, acting upon that stored information or structure. From the point of view of memory research, then, musical structure and musical process can not be separated, and a theory of music concerned with asking the crucial questions about music cannot afford to accept the conventional distinction between structure (artefact) and process (procedure). The question is not whether or not, but how structure and process are related in musical memory. III Having just arrived at the top of the magical mountain we are climbing, let us look around, to see what we have left behind us, and what we have achieved. First, we have left behind us (rather far in the distance, I am afraid) this century's music theory, including twentieth-century music theory; or, to be more fair, we have left behind its way of posing and answering questions, though not the substance of its questions. Second, we have established the need for a theory of musical memory, or a musical semantics. Third, we have indicated that in order to ask (and even more, to answer) questions about structure in music, one needs to ask (and even more, to answer) questions about process in music. And finally we have committed ourselves to showing that all this is not only conceivable, but also possible, and that there is a technology by which one can approach the questions posed by a procedural theory of music experimentally. It is impossible, at this point, to enter into an extensive critique of traditional theory and its extensions into twentieth-century theory. However, I shall intro- duce the definition of a theory of music that I call procedural e contrario, by pointing out the crucial ways in which it differs from traditional theory. Tradi- tional theory has developed into what, epistemologically speaking, are three loosely connected branches. These branches of music theory represent partial theories, or descriptions, of musical thought. Let me label them the branches of an initial-state, a goal-state, and an intermediate-state description of musical thought. All of these descriptions are essentially syntax-centred and, in a way to be specified, reductionistic. An initial-state description of musical thought is pre-compositional; it is concemed with compositional resources (often, with some exaggeration, called musical systems). A goal-state description of musical thought is an analytical 13 description of produced music. Only in its most rigorous form is such a descrip- tion free from the inconsistency of expressing, at times, the view of a precomposi- tionally instructed composer, and at other times the view of an idealised listener subservient to such a composer; usually, the description vacillates between these points of view. Both theories mentioned so far deal with musical competence, that is, unobservable knowledge. Up to the present day, the practitioners of these theories have not cared to substantiate their hypotheses by way of investigating actual human performances. (Actually, these branches of theory are concerned with hypotheses concerning syntactic competence only, viz. with operations of the musical intelligence that provide the opportunity to transform some present stimulus configuration.) Finally, an intermediate-state description of musical thought results from an attempt to explicate the link between initial musical states (such as plans and resources) and goal states (such as scores). This kind of description is formulated on the basis of assumptions as to what constitutes music-syntactic competence, usually in the form of computer programmes for composition.* To the extent that intermediate-state descriptions neglect actual human performances (although they pretend to model them), they, too, cannot do justice to the complete scope of compositional, and even less musical, thought. The point important to my argument is that although all of these partial theories implicitly or explicitly claim to account for musical thought, the creators of these theories have not cared to develop a methodology by which the competence hypotheses the theories state can be substantiated empirically, viz. as hypotheses having psychological validity with regard to observable human problem solving. In my comprehensive view of music theory as a theory of musical thought, its products, and the relation of these products to thought processes, the lack of such a methodology is synonymous not merely with incompleteness, but with reductionism. By this harsh judgement I mean that traditional music theory has never raised the question of what is the function of musical syntax within the framework of the total memory system involved in musical listening, composi- tion, and reproduction. Instead, the theory reduces musical thought as well as musical products to syntactic structures and shows itself incapable of dealing with semantic and sonological processes, that is, with the reconstruction of a music's past in semantic memory, and with the construction of perceptions and images in perceptual memory. Consequently, the theory fails even in its own domain, that of explicating musical products adequately, viz. comprehensively. I have indicated that syntactic rules are necessary in music in order to relate transmitted sound to stored meaning. In contrast to this function of syntax. music theorists have always treated syntax as an end in itself. Music theorists have dealt with syntax as if its function, linking the transmission terminal of music (viz. the vocal tract, instruments, and the auditory system) to the receiving terminal (viz. musical memory), were of negligible relevance. However, it is evident that the constant development of musical rule systems and styles, sociological reasons aside, takes place because developmentally, the two terminals are in no pre-established harmony. Musical art is the human attempt to match the two terminals. Music-syntactic rules are necessary precisely because without *For an example of initial-state theory, see Allen Forte, The Structure of Atonal AIusic (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1973). Goal-state descriptions of music abound and have been formulated from various points of view and with differing degrees of explicitness. For a theory of goal-state analysis see Jean-Jacques Nattiez, Fondements d'une semiologie de la musique (Paris: Union Generale d'Editions, 1975). Intermediate-state theory, too, has espoused differing points of view; for examples, see Lejaren A. Hiller and Leonard M. Isaacson, Experimental Music (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1959); lannis Xenakis, Formalized Music (Bloomington: Indiana University, 1972; original French ed., 1963); G. M. Koenig, "Project Two: A Programme for Musical Composition", Electronic Music Reports, no. 2 (Utrecht: Institute of Sonology, Winter 1970)- and Stephen W. Smoliar, "A Parallel Processing Model of Musical Structures", Technical Report no. TR-242 (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Artificial Intelligence Laboratory? 1971), 14 them "the number of messages that the most prolific intellect could send [would be] severely limited by the ... rather small number of distinctively different signals that a poor transmission system can cope with" (Liberman, 1975, p. 4). The fact that in comparison to linguistic syntax, musical syntax is seemingly much more loose simply reflects the evidence that the sonic transmission system used in music is comparatively less limited than the phonemic system used by language. In other words, there is less need in music to impose syntactic con- straints since the sonic transmission terminal of musical systems can cope with a greater variety of materials.* Nevertheless, the unlimitedness of the number of possible sonic messages in music is an illusion of technicians. However expanded our sonic vocabulary might become, due to technical innovation, it could never match the number of intellectually possible messages that our stored experience and cognitive machinery (or "intellect") can generate. And as long as the two terminals, the sonic and the semantic terminal, are thus disparate, the necessity for syntax to exist is a reality. Stating the problem of musical syntax this way certainly raises some questions in and about music theory. To answer these questions one need not speculate. There now exists a methodology that enables music theorists to enlarge the scope of their inquiry, and to proceed toward an empirical verification of their hypo- theses concerming what is music-syntactic competence. In general terms, this methodology concerns the explication of music-theoretical statements, as well as the explication of empirical records of musical behaviour, in terms of pro- gramming languages. In particular, I am thinking of two recent developments. The first is the attempt to explicate informally-stated syntactic theories (as is being done by Stephen Smoliar and Michael Kassler, who deal with the theories of Heinrich Schenker); the second, the attempt to explicate performance records of musical subjects in terms of programmes called production systems (as is being done by this author). As was clearly seen by Chomsky, only an explicit syntactic theory is falsifiable. To make hypotheses concerning musical syntax explicit is valuable mainly because it affords one the opportumty to realise the limitations of the music-syntactic component, compared to the scope of the larger set of components required for an explication of musical thought processes. Today, there exists the possibility of dealing with theoretical problems of music in a more truly comprehensive, as well as in an experimental, fashion. Many factors, artistic, scientific, and technological, have contributed to this possibility; I name only those that seem to me to be the most important ones. First, we have lost a great deal of the ethnomusicological naivetW that formerly sanctioned the exclusive concern with (European) art music in music theory. Second, electronic sound synthesis, while it has regretfully not led us to abandon theoretical models that are really (incomplete) models of notated music only, has at least engendered the concem for a theory of tone colour and, more generally, of musical sound comprehension. The existence of the tape medium of musical (re-)production has prompted an acoulogical viewpoint (that of P. Schaeffer) to arise that, since it intentionally disregards the cultural variety of sound sources, leads to the postulate that sonological universals exist. Such a viewpoint prompts the theorist to deal with the role of syntactic constructs as forming a link between musical perception and music-semantic understanding. Third, the invention of digital sound synthesis permits new kinds of sonic designs to arise and provides research facilities of unknown accuracy both for the investigation into musical processes and musical structures. Fourth, information-processing psychology *There is some evidence that suggests that short-term memory is a property of the linguistic, rather than a musical, processor, or at least that short-term memory is of less relevance for musical processing than it is for language processing. This could be due to the fact that musical information is directly written into contextual (intermediate-term) memory and long-term memory, there being no pre-fabricated music-syntactic units. The problems of musical syntax and of musical short-term memory are closely related problems. 15 has developed a precise methodology for formulating and testing a theory of musical memory, and developments in modal logic have brought forth the attempt to explicate music-semantic memory contents by way of empirically testable constructs called networks. Finally, developmental psychology, through its merger with information-processing theory, has opened up new perspectives for a theory of musical learning and instruction both of which requii-e the assistance of the theory of music.* lV I have indicated that it is the task of a theory of music to relate the knowledge we have about musical structures to our knowledge concerning the mental processes and the memory system required for producing and/or understanding such structures. In order to avoid reductionism of any sort, a theory of music has to acknowledge the autonomy that characterises musical structures in two respects. First, such structures (especially when notated) acquire a culturally. i.e. sociologically caused, autonomy that makes them irreducible to either acoustic, psychological, or even sociological phenomena. Second, stored in human (long-term) memory through learning and experience, musical structures become the actual knowledge base of a specific kind of competence different from both linguistic and logical competence, viz. musical competence. From a theoretical point of view, this competence is less a scientifically established reality than a hypothetical construct that remains to be verified empirically. As is true for the linguistic competence of native speakers of a language, the musical competence of practising musicians is an "intrinsic tacit knowledge'" (according to Chomsky) that is not directly observable. Competence hypotheses may not be open to proof, but they are certainly open to falsification by way ol developmental studies and studies in problem solving. By designing appropriate task environments in which controlled musical processes take place, the intrinsic tacit knowledge of musicians can be elicited and made observable. To observe musical competence-in-action is the task of psychomusicology; to observe its growth, the task of developmental psychomusicology.*, To summarise, a comprehensive theory of music is a science comprising two interrelated subdisciplines: first, a theory of musical structures, or musicology; and second, a theory of cognitive processes resulting in musical structures, or psychomusicology. Musicology formulates structural descriptions of musical artifacts (this term taken in the broad sense of all possible sonic designs); to be operationally relevant, these descriptions must be so formulated that they can serve as descriptions, or sufficiency analyses, of the competence component of an actual performance system simulating a musical listener. For brevity's sake, let us assume that these descriptions form a system S (for 'structures"). Psycho- musicology formulates structural descriptions, or models, of musical activities, in the particular sense of problem-solving activities; let us assume that these descriptions form a system A (for "activities"). We can then formiulate the following rules of co-ordination for musicology and psychomusicology (Laske, 1975); I. Every assertion in S (musicology) is independent of the assertions in A (psychomusicology), and no problem in A is a problem in S; *For a theory of tone colour, see chapter 4 of Robert Cogan and Pozzi Escot, Seonic Designl (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1976). For a statement of the acoulogical viewpoint, see Pierre Schaeffer, Traitl des objets musicaux (Paris: Editions du Seuil, 1966). For a reference concerning the information-processing methodology, see Allen Newell and Herbert A. Simon, Human Problem Solving (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1972), as well as Allen Newell, "Production Systems: Models of Control Structures", in Visual Information Processing, ed. William G. Chase (New York: Academic Press, 1973), pp. 463-515. Finally for the use of modal logic in musical semantics, see Kunst, 1976. tConcerning the correspondence between the operational levels of intelligence and thie stages of memory development, see Piaget, 1973, passim. 16 II. Every assertion or problem in S (musicology) produces a problem in A (psychomusicology), but the solution of the problem in A can only be obtained by the methods peculiar to A. A question remains about what it means to co-ordinate the two sciences, of musical structures and activities, and whether the job of co-ordinating them falls to a third superordinate science. Regarding language research with respect to this question, one finds there is a science called linguistics (which is a science of language structures), and a science called psycholinguistics (which is a science of the mental processes required for producing and understanding language structures). There seems to be no third, superordinate science for relating these two disciplines. I think that the problem of co-ordinating system S (musicology) with system A (psychomusicology) must be solved on two levels, a methodological and a substantive level. To make clear what I mean, let me now assume that the theories called S and A are automata having a definable input and output. That is, let me assume that S and A can be viewed procedurally, as performance mechanisms. On the first level, the input to S is a particular music that is in sounding or notational form. S itself is a music analyser. Upon receiving some musical input, the automaton S initiates an interpretive process called music analysis. The output of S, then, is a theory of the input, i.e. a set of hypotheses about the structure of the input. In most cases, this set of hypotheses is a structural descrip- tion of the music. Such a description can take a variety of forms, especially with regard to the degree of formal rigour it exhibits. I shall not discuss here the many different forms a music analysis can take; I only wish to say that, naturally, the more formal and explicit the analysis, the more testable is the set of hypotheses that it represents. (Merely referring to some notational representation of a music and appealing to the intrinsic musical knowledge of the (score-reading) reader of the analysis is not a sufficient verification procedure.) On the methodological level of the co-ordination of S and A, the output of S is taken to be the input of A, and the output of A is the verification of the input hypotheses, or musical (micro-) theory produced by S. A, then, is a verification procedure for outputs of S. (There is ultimately no other verification procedure for a music analysis than a procedure that establishes empirically that listeners do indeed hear a music as the analysis says they do. Therefore it is crucial to make it clear in the analysis exactly what it is that the listeners are thought to comprehend.) To understand clearly what it means to verify in A a structural description produced by S, let us consider more closely the process of music analysis, or theory formulation. Music analysis is a complex transformation task in the pursuit of which a sounding or notationally represented music is transformed from its input representation into a natural-language and/or formal language representation. (Graphic schemes, such as notational fragments, may comple- ment the analysis.) The process by which this transformation is accomplished is to a large extent taken for granted, and thus poorly understood at present; it can be studied psychomusicologically. Ideally, the music analysis produced by S is a sufficiency analysis. That is, the analysis is the formulation of a mechanism that is sufficient for understanding the analysed music. A sufficiency analysis concems an idealised performance system, viz. one whose memory limitations and music-strategical specifics have been disregarded. Consequently, the result of the analysis process activated by S is not an efficient and necessary, only a sufficient, minimal mechanism for understanding the analysed music. With regard to the verification of the analysis, the actual processes which are required for implementing the analysis as a procedure for understanding music have not been specified. What can it mean to verify a sufficiency analysis of music except to test its psychological validity with regard to actual understanding systems, i.e. humans? The fact that most existing music analyses are, or seem to be, very 17 complex does not mean that they are not in principle verifiable. What makes most of them unverifiable is their cumbersome and sloppy form: most are not sufficiency analyses. But this deficiency of music analyses is not a burden that can be placed upon psychomusicology. If musicology indeed is a science, then it is up to musicologists to provide proper input to psychomusicology, i.e verifiable theories. If musicology fails to comply with the methodological requirement to provide verifiable, or at least falsifiable, theories, then it is simply inefficient. I shall now reformulate the co-ordination rules I and II in order to summarise their methodological content: I. A structural description of some music produced by S is a sufficiency analysis, i.e. the formulation of a mechanism sufficient for, but not necessarily efficient for, understanding the analysed music. The description is or implies a set of hypotheses concerning musical competence. Com- petential hypotheses are independent of assertions concerning psychological processes, formulated in A. However, the operational relevance of these hypotheses is determined by their usefulness in, and significance for, verifying the elements of competential knowledge that they postulate. I the set of hypotheses implied by a structural description is not verifiable, then the hypotheses must remain unconfirmed. II. (a) Every description problem in S, or structural description of some music formulated by S, produces a twofold psychomusicological problem in A. The first problem is general; it concerns the process of music analysis by which structural descriptions are formulated. The second problem is specific; it concerns the psychological validity of claims made in a particular music analysis regarding the existence of musical competence instantiated by the music. (b) With regard to the first problem, psychomusicological research must deal with the fundamental processes of music analysis in order to ascertain their nature and function. With regard to the second problenm, psychomusicological research must provide a set of physical task environments in which the elements of competential knowledge claimed to exist by S can be elicited and verified. (c) If the psychological validity of a musicological hypothesis remains unverified, then either a deficiency in formulating the hypothesis, or in testing it, or both, has occurred. Whatever the deficiency. the hypothesis remains speculative. (d) Finally, successful verification of a hypothesis of S in A causes a problem of developmental psychomusicology to arise, viz. the problem of what the ontogenesis is of musical structures such as those formulated by S and verified by A. Psychomusicology has been called a verification procedure for outputs of S. Because of the recent emergence of this science, only very simple hypotheses can be verified at this time. However, there is every reason to believe that psycho- musicology is capable of developing to a level of maturity where complex musicological hypotheses can be tested. The theoretical task, therefore, is two- fold: first, producing verifiable musicological hypotheses in S; and second. developing psychomusicological verification procedures in A. Let me now discuss the second level of the co-ordination of S and A, viz. the substantive level. In terms of subject matter, the linkage of musical structures (stored in memory) to musical processes (activated by the musician) is just what the making of music requires of humans. The ability to effect this linkage is what is called "understanding music". (To take an example, consider the performer giving a recital. The performer has the music before him in notational form, or else has committed its structure to memory. His task in both cases consists of 18 assembling a performance programme that takes the structural description of the music as input and realises it, i.e. transforms it into some procedural represent- ation in terms of which sound producing processes can be initiated. When capable of assembling such a programme and of using it the performer is said to "under- stand music" or to "be a musician".) Speaking in substantive terms, a theory of music can be said to accomplish in theoretical form what the active musician does in actuality. The theory of music is a theory of musical knowledge or, operationally speaking, of musical understanding. The theory shows how struc- ture and process relate in musical activities. A second, equally important concern of the theory of music is how structure and process come to relate in musical activities, viz. how the mature capacity for relating the seemingly independent aspects of music is acquired by a human. In asking this developmental question, the theory of music operates on both the methodological and substantive levels simultaneously, merging with the science of developmental psychomusicology. In as far as it is a theory of musical competence, a theory of music ultimately requires the existence of a theory of the acquisition of musical competence, to substantiate its claims fully. This entails that the dividing line between the theory of music and the empirical science of developmental psychomusicology may be difficult to draw. It is the task of developmental psychomusicology to verify hypotheses concerning musical competence. Such hypotheses are not exclusively embodied in the structural descriptions of musical artefacts produced by experts; they may equally well be hypotheses conceming the elementary musical competence of children and adolescents, and the development of musical competence to maturity. One cannot scientifically understand musical artifacts without understanding the development to maturity of the musical competence which such artefacts presuppose. To summarise, a theory of music is ultimately an empirical science that formulates and tests hypotheses about the nature of musical competence*. The theory of music also investigates what distinguishes the functioning of musical competence from that of other kinds of competence, for instance linguistic and logical competence. The theory of music is therefore an interdisciplinary enterprise. It is, itself, one of the many sub- disciplines of a comprehensive theory of human knowledge, or a scientific epistemology. V Let me close with some very general remarks concerning musical instruction, in order to demonstrate the practical significance of psychomusicology. Musical instruction is a wide field. To gain some orientation in this field, let us distinguish three different problem areas: curriculum design, strategies for practical instruc- tion, and theory of instruction. Although a procedural theory of music has somiething to contribute to all of these, in what follows I restrict myself to the third-mentioned topic, the theory of instruction. By "instruction" I mean, following Resnick (1976, p. 51), any environmental conditions that are deliberately arranged to foster increases in competence. Put most simply, the relation between psychomusicology (as a study of the mental processes that result in musical structures) and a theory of instruction is that the former constitutes, or at least ought to constitute, the scientific basis of the latter. One can consider the experimental situations studied in psychomusicological research as approxima- tions of real-world (musical) tasks. Conversely, one can structure classroom *Hypotheses concerning musical competence do not result from musicological research alone; they may equally result from research in psychomusicology and developmental psychomusicology. An example of hypotheses formulated within the framework of psychomusicology is given in Laske, 1976, Introduction to Psychomusicology, passim. To derive hypotheses concerning musical competence from other than musicological sources is obviously necessary for studies in music analysis; music analysis itself does not formulate hypotheses that can be used to understand music-analytical processes. 19 experiences in such a way that they yield insight into learning which is both theoretical (for the teacher-experimenter) and practical (for the student-subject). Clearly, there is only one way to free the student from being the subject of instruction in the pejorative sense, that is, a victim: one must engage his natural heuristic system, his problem-solving apparatus, in the instructional process. To do so one must know what it means to learn, more specifically, what it means to learn music. And in order to understand what it means to learn music, one must first of all understand what it means to perform a musical activity. That is, to define a model of a music learner, one needs a performance model, or a model of the musical activity of a musical expert. Three theories are thus involved: first, a theory of activity (performance); second, a theory of instruction; and third, a theory of learning. I have just indicated the relation of the first theory to the third (performance/learning). As to the relation between the second and the third theory (instruction/learning), it would be mistaken to think that the development of a theory of instruction can not progress before one has formulated a comprehensive theory of learning. "What is needed is a model that captures the essential features of that part of the learning process that is tapped by an instructional task" (Atkinson, 1976, p. 107). To identify such features, one needs to have identified the set of fundamental processes which enters into the performance of the task to be taught. In terms of psychomusicology, one needs to have performed a task analysis. A task analysis, in the psychomusicological sense, is an analysis of the problem determinants, the sources of difficulty, and the kinds of knowledge required for pursuing a task successfully. There are two kinds of task analysis: abstract or conceptual, and empirical task analysis (Resnick, 1976, p. 64). In the former, the analysis concerns idealised performances; one seeks to discover what is a sufficient mechanism, ideally in the form of a computer-simulation programme, for performing the task successfully*. In the second, one verifies or disproves and amplifies the theory formulated in the conceptual analysis by investigating actual performances of subjects in the task under consideration. The empirical mateirial for such an investigation can be of different kinds: it may consist of thinking- aloud protocols, action protocols, reaction-time data, sketches, and other kinds of behavioural traces.t The purpose of an empirical task analysis is to identify those fundamental processes, from the set of processes postulated by Tie conceptual task analysis, that an expert performer has actually used in Ilis pursuit of a task. Once such processes are known and verified, they can be taught; teaching successfully means teaching the heuristic processes of experts (Famham-Diggory, 1972, p. 83). Instruction, you will agree, is concerned with processes. nin music, instructioni is concerned with fostering the growth of an inner music-generating system that fits some musical environment to the point at which the system becomes capable of modifying the environment. Whether there is a natural "music acquisition device" that samples the sonic environment, formulates hypotheses as to the nature of music, and outputs examples of these hypotheses, correcting them by experience, is not known. But it is a good hypothesis to follow because it elucidates the problems of musical instruction. If there is a natural music acquisition system, then we want to make use of it in teaching. Above, I have utilised the structure/process distinction to clarify problems *The analogy to music analysis is apparent: a music analysis ideally is a sufficient mechanisn tfoi understanding some musical artifact. However, the verification of such a mechanism falls outside ots musicology, viz. into psychomusicology. tProtocols in the sense of cognitive psychology are lists of natural or formal language statemilenits. Thinking-aloud protocols are documentations of verbally mediated thought as it occurs during a problem-solving session. Action protocols document the actions taken by a problem solver Reaction-time data are recorded measurements of the time subjects take to respond to the onset of some physical or symbolic stimulus. 20 of a theory of music. It is not astonishing to find that this distinction reoccurs in educational controversies, viz. in the form of a distinction between teaching processes of thought versus teaching their products. One would not expect a procedural theory of music to endorse the teaching of ready-made products and facts as the primary task of instruction. Let us turn to the processes. In accordance with Farnham-Doggory (op. cit., p. 81), I distinguish three kinds of thinking process that occur in education (her text, my examples): Type 1. A behavioural recipe for obtaining a solution (e.g. for writing a harmony exercise); Type 2. A logical process existing in the subject matter (e.g. some theory of modulation); Type 3. A process of reasoning that is psychological in nature (e.g. the process of thinking about, and solving, a problem of modulation, as distinct from a theory of modulation). The first two kinds of process apply formal rules; one can write programmes (algorithms) for them. The third process applies rules of thumb, i.e. a heuristic; one can attempt to state a set of heuristic rules in terms of a problem-solving theory formulated as a simulation programme. Many theories of education that have dealt with the first two processes have been implemented; by contrast, the teaching of the heuristic processes of experts has not been attempted. The reason for this is simple: the theory of heuristic processes, known as theory of problem solving, is relatively young, and its extension into the theory of instruction is just beginning (Atkinson, 1976; Resnick, 1976). I call a theory that formulates models of a musical learner and tests them empirically a theory of musical instruction. Such a theory is a natural consequence of a theory of problem solving that incorporates adequate notions of human memory. What is the relation between a model of musical activity, as formulated by psychomusicology, and models of a musical learner? A model of some activity, or performance model, is a model of expert performances. Such a model is a prerequisite for evaluating and studying the inexpert performances of novices, for the purpose of arriving at models of learning. In order to formulate a model of a learner (for some task domain), one must know what the fundamental processes are by which instructional goals are achieved. "In order to deal effect- ively with educational problems, we need theories that tell us how knowledge is represented in memory, how information is retrieved from that knowledge structure, how new information is added to the structure, and how the system can expand that knowledge by a self-generative process" (Atkinson, op. cit., p. 82). Clearly, at this point our understanding of the musical learning process, and of music acquisition, is so limited that it seems impossible to identify truly effective strategies for musical instruction. And where such strategies exist in naive (common-sense) form, one cannot say why they work. However, as I shall demonstrate in a subsequent paper, the analysis of tasks as undertaken by psychomusicology provides us with means for understanding learning experiences better, structuring them more adequately, and building curricula on the basis of insight into the natural heuristic system of students, instead of designing curricula in terms of sets of artefacts produced by people long dead, or of facts and historical legends. One might say that all of traditional music analysis and music theory is a repertory of unconfirmed hypotheses as to how humans think musically; the behavioural evidence these hypotheses refer to is in the form of musical artefacts. It is the task of psychomusicology to test, and confirm or reject, these hypotheses, and in so doing provide a scientific basis for musical instruction. University of Illinois, Urbana, IL 61801, USA. 21 References Atkinson, R. C. (1976). Adaptive Instructional Systems: Some Attempts to Optimize the Learning Process. In Cognition and Instruction, pp. 81-108. Edited by David Klahr. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Brown, A. L. (1975). The Development of Memory: Knowing, Knowing About Knowing, and Knowing How to Know. In Advances in Child Development and Behavior, Vol. 10, pp. 104-152. Edited by Hayne W. Reese. New York: Academic Press. Farnham-Diggory, S. (1972). Cognitive Processes in Education. New YoIk: Harper & Row. Kunst, J. (1976). Making Sense in Music. Unpublished manuscript; to appear in Interface (Amsterdam). Vol. 5, no. 1 (Summer 1976). Laske, 0. E. (1975). Introduction to a Generative Theory of Music. Sonological Reports, no. 1. Utrecht: Institute of Sonology, 1972; republication. - (1975). Toward a Theory of Musical Cognition. Interface (Amsterdam.) Vol. 4, no. 2 (Winter). (1975). On Psychomusicology. International Review of the Aesthetics and Sociology of Music (Zagreb). Vol. 6, no. 2 (Winter). -(1976). Introduction to Psychomusicology. Unpublished manuscript; in In Theory Only. Ann Arbor, Michigan. Vol. 2, 1-2. - (1976). Toward a Theory of Musical Instruction. Unpublished manuscript; to appear in In Theory Only. Ann Arbor, Michigan. Vol. 2, 3-4. - (1976). On Some Developmental Problems of Auditory Imagery. International Review of the Aesthetics and Sociology of Music (Zagreb). Vol. 7, no. I (Summer). - (1976). Verification and Sociological Interpretation in Musicology. Interna- tional Review of the Aesthetics and Sociology of Music (Zagreb). Vol. 8, no. I (Summer). Libermann, A. M. (1975). Introduction to the Conference. In The Role of Speech in Language, pp. 3-7. Edited by James F. Kavanagh and James E. Cutting. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Lindsay, P. H. and Norman, Donald, A. (1972). Human Information Processing: An Introduction to Psychology. New York: Academic Press. Massaro, D. W. (1975). Experimental Psychology and Infornation Processing. Chicago: Rand McNally, 1975. Piaget, J. (1964). Development and Learning. In Piaget Rediscovered, pp. 7-19. Edited by Richard E. Ripple and V. Rockcastle. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Piaget, J. and Inhelder, B. (1973). Memory and Intelligence. New York: Basic Books. Resnick, L. B. (1976). Task Analysis in Instructional Design: Some Cases from Mathematics. In Cognition and Instruction, pp. 51-80. Edited by David Klahr. Hillsdale, N. J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Simon, H. A. (1962). An Information-Processing Theory of Intellectual Develop- ment. In Thought in the Young Child, pp. 137-161. Edited by William Kessen and Clementina Kuhlman. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development, Vol. 27. Lafayette, Ind.: Child Development Publications. 22 </meta-value>
</custom-meta>
</custom-meta-wrap>
</article-meta>
</front>
<back>
<notes>
<p>*A music-grammatical rule claims universal validity within the scope of some musical tradition, whereas a stylistic rule is part of a set of rules defining a personal style.</p>
<p>*For an excellent overview of the developmental literature, and for considerations of involuntai-y versus deliberate memory, see Brown (1975); for the close relationship of memory and intelligenc (musically speaking, semantics and syntax), see Piaget (1973), especially pp. 400-401t</p>
<p>*For an example of initial-state theory, see Allen Forte,
<italic>The Structure of Atonal Music</italic>
(New Haven: Yale University Press, 1973). Goal-state descriptions of music abound and have been formulated from various points of view and with differing degrees of explicitness. For a theory of goal-state analysis see Jean-Jacques Nattiez,
<italic>Fondements d'une semiologie de la musique</italic>
(Paris: Union Generale d'Editions, 1975). Intermediate-state theory, too, has espoused differing points of view; for examples, see Lejaren A. Hiller and Leonard M. Isaacson,
<italic>Experimental Music</italic>
(New York: McGraw-Hill, 1959); lannis Xenakis,
<italic>Formalized Music</italic>
(Bloomington: Indiana University, 1972; original French ed., 1963); G. M. Koenig, "Project Two: A Programme for Musical Composition",
<italic>Electronic Music Reports,</italic>
no. 2 (Utrecht: Institute of Sonology, Winter 1970)- and Stephen W. Smoliar, "A Parallel Processing Model of Musical Structures", Technical Report no. TR-242 (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Artificial Intelligence Laboratory? 1971),</p>
<p>*There is some evidence that suggests that short-term memory is a property of the linguistic, rather than a musical, processor, or at least that short-term memory is of less relevance for musical processing than it is for language processing. This could be due to the fact that musical information is directly written into contextual (intermediate-term) memory and long-term memory, there being no pre-fabricated music-syntactic units. The problems of musical syntax and of musical short-term memory are closely related problems.</p>
<p>*For a theory of tone colour, see chapter 4 of Robert Cogan and Pozzi Escot,
<italic>Seonic Designl</italic>
(Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1976). For a statement of the acoulogical viewpoint, see Pierre Schaeffer,
<italic>Traitl des objets musicaux</italic>
(Paris: Editions du Seuil, 1966). For a reference concerning the information-processing methodology, see Allen Newell and Herbert A. Simon,
<bold>
<bold>
<italic>Human</italic>
</bold>
</bold>
<italic>Problem Solving</italic>
(Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1972), as well as Allen Newell, "Production Systems: Models of Control Structures", in
<italic>Visual Information Processing,</italic>
ed. William G. Chase (New York: Academic Press, 1973), pp. 463-515. Finally for the use of modal logic in musical semantics, see Kunst, 1976.</p>
<p>†Concerning the correspondence between the operational levels of intelligence and
<bold>thie</bold>
stages of memory development, see Piaget, 1973, passim.</p>
<p>*Hypotheses concerning musical competence do not result from musicological research alone; they may equally result from research in psychomusicology and developmental psychomusicology. An example of hypotheses formulated within the framework of psychomusicology is given in Laske, 1976,
<italic>Introduction to Psychomusicology,</italic>
passim. To derive hypotheses concerning musical competence from other than musicological sources is obviously necessary for studies in music analysis; music analysis itself does not formulate hypotheses that can be used to understand music-analytical processes.</p>
<p>*The analogy to music analysis is apparent: a music analysis ideally is a sufficient mechanisn
<bold>tfoi</bold>
understanding some musical artifact. However, the verification of such a mechanism falls outside ots musicology, viz. into psychomusicology.</p>
<p>†Protocols in the sense of cognitive psychology are lists of natural or formal language statemilenits. Thinking-aloud protocols are documentations of verbally mediated thought as it occurs during a problem-solving session. Action protocols document the actions taken by a problem solver Reaction-time data are recorded measurements of the time subjects take to respond to the onset of some physical or symbolic stimulus.</p>
</notes>
<ref-list>
<ref>
<citation citation-type="book" xlink:type="simple">
<name name-style="western">
<surname>Atkinson, R. C.</surname>
</name>
(
<year>1976</year>
).
<article-title>Adaptive Instructional Systems: Some Attempts to Optimize the Learning Process</article-title>
. In
<source>Cognition and Instruction</source>
, pp.
<fpage>81</fpage>
-
<lpage>108</lpage>
. Edited by
<name name-style="western">
<surname>David Klahr</surname>
</name>
.
<publisher-loc>Hillsdale, N.J.</publisher-loc>
:
<publisher-name>Lawrence Erlbaum Associates</publisher-name>
.</citation>
</ref>
<ref>
<citation citation-type="book" xlink:type="simple">
<name name-style="western">
<surname>Brown, A. L.</surname>
</name>
(
<year>1975</year>
).
<article-title>The Development of Memory: Knowing, Knowing About Knowing, and Knowing How to Know</article-title>
. In
<source>Advances in Child Development and Behavior</source>
, Vol. 10, pp.
<fpage>104</fpage>
-
<lpage>152</lpage>
. Edited by
<name name-style="western">
<surname>Hayne W. Reese</surname>
</name>
.
<publisher-loc>New York</publisher-loc>
:
<publisher-name>Academic Press</publisher-name>
.</citation>
</ref>
<ref>
<citation citation-type="book" xlink:type="simple">
<name name-style="western">
<surname>Farnham-Diggory, S.</surname>
</name>
(
<year>1972</year>
).
<source>Cognitive Processes in Education</source>
.
<publisher-loc>New York</publisher-loc>
:
<publisher-name>Harper & Row</publisher-name>
.</citation>
</ref>
<ref>
<citation citation-type="other" xlink:type="simple">Kunst, J. (1976). Making Sense in Music. Unpublished manuscript; to appear in Interface (Amsterdam). Vol. 5, no. 1 (Summer 1976).</citation>
</ref>
<ref>
<citation citation-type="book" xlink:type="simple">
<name name-style="western">
<surname>Laske, O. E.</surname>
</name>
(
<year>1975</year>
).
<source>Introduction to a Generative Theory of Music</source>
. Sonological Reports, no. 1.
<publisher-loc>Utrecht</publisher-loc>
:
<publisher-name>Institute of Sonology</publisher-name>
, 1972; republication.</citation>
</ref>
<ref>
<citation citation-type="journal" xlink:type="simple">
<name name-style="western">
<surname>Laske, O. E.</surname>
</name>
(
<year>1975</year>
).
<article-title>Toward a Theory of Musical Cognition</article-title>
.
<source>Interface (Amsterdam.)</source>
<volume>Vol. 4</volume>
,
<issue>no. 2 (Winter)</issue>
.</citation>
</ref>
<ref>
<citation citation-type="journal" xlink:type="simple">
<name name-style="western">
<surname>Laske, O. E.</surname>
</name>
(
<year>1975</year>
).
<article-title>On Psychomusicology</article-title>
.
<source>International Review of the Aesthetics and Sociology of Music (Zagreb)</source>
.
<volume>Vol. 6</volume>
,
<issue>no. 2 (Winter)</issue>
.</citation>
</ref>
<ref>
<citation citation-type="other" xlink:type="simple">Laske, 0. E.(1976). Introduction to Psychomusicology. Unpublished manuscript; in In Theory Only. Ann Arbor, Michigan. Vol. 2, 1-2.</citation>
</ref>
<ref>
<citation citation-type="other" xlink:type="simple">Laske, 0. E. (1976). Toward a Theory of Musical Instruction. Unpublished manuscript; to appear in In Theory Only. Ann Arbor, Michigan. Vol. 2, 3-4.</citation>
</ref>
<ref>
<citation citation-type="journal" xlink:type="simple">
<name name-style="western">
<surname>Laske, O. E.</surname>
</name>
(
<year>1976</year>
).
<article-title>On Some Developmental Problems of Auditory Imagery</article-title>
.
<source>International Review of the Aesthetics and Sociology of Music (Zagreb)</source>
.
<volume>Vol. 7</volume>
,
<issue>no. 1 (Summer)</issue>
.</citation>
</ref>
<ref>
<citation citation-type="journal" xlink:type="simple">
<name name-style="western">
<surname>Laske, O. E.</surname>
</name>
(
<year>1976</year>
).
<article-title>Verification and Sociological Interpretation in Musicology</article-title>
.
<source>International Review of the Aesthetics and Sociology of Music (Zagreb)</source>
.
<volume>Vol. 8</volume>
,
<issue>no. 1 (Summer)</issue>
.</citation>
</ref>
<ref>
<citation citation-type="book" xlink:type="simple">
<name name-style="western">
<surname>Libermann, A. M.</surname>
</name>
(
<year>1975</year>
).
<article-title>Introduction to the Conference</article-title>
. In
<source>The Role of Speech in Language</source>
, pp.
<fpage>3</fpage>
-
<lpage>7</lpage>
. Edited by
<name name-style="western">
<surname>James F. Kavanagh</surname>
</name>
and
<name name-style="western">
<surname>James E. Cutting</surname>
</name>
.
<publisher-loc>Cambridge, Mass.</publisher-loc>
:
<publisher-name>MIT Press</publisher-name>
.</citation>
</ref>
<ref>
<citation citation-type="book" xlink:type="simple">
<name name-style="western">
<surname>Lindsay, P. H.</surname>
</name>
and
<name name-style="western">
<surname>Norman Donald, A.</surname>
</name>
(
<year>1972</year>
).
<source>Human Information Processing: An Introduction to Psychology</source>
.
<publisher-loc>New York</publisher-loc>
:
<publisher-name>Academic Press</publisher-name>
.</citation>
</ref>
<ref>
<citation citation-type="book" xlink:type="simple">
<name name-style="western">
<surname>Massaro, D. W.</surname>
</name>
(
<year>1975</year>
).
<source>Experimental Psychology and Infornation Processing</source>
.
<publisher-loc>Chicago</publisher-loc>
:
<publisher-name>Rand McNally</publisher-name>
, 1975.</citation>
</ref>
<ref>
<citation citation-type="book" xlink:type="simple">
<name name-style="western">
<surname>Piaget, J.</surname>
</name>
(
<year>1964</year>
).
<article-title>Development and Learning</article-title>
. In
<source>Piaget Rediscovered</source>
, pp.
<fpage>7</fpage>
-
<lpage>19</lpage>
. Edited by
<name name-style="western">
<surname>Richard E. Ripple</surname>
</name>
and
<name name-style="western">
<surname>V. Rockcastle</surname>
</name>
.
<publisher-loc>Ithaca</publisher-loc>
:
<publisher-name>Cornell University Press</publisher-name>
.</citation>
</ref>
<ref>
<citation citation-type="book" xlink:type="simple">
<name name-style="western">
<surname>Piaget, J.</surname>
</name>
and
<name name-style="western">
<surname>Inhelder, B.</surname>
</name>
(
<year>1973</year>
).
<source>Memory and Intelligence</source>
.
<publisher-loc>New York</publisher-loc>
:
<publisher-name>Basic Books</publisher-name>
.</citation>
</ref>
<ref>
<citation citation-type="book" xlink:type="simple">
<name name-style="western">
<surname>Resnick, L. B.</surname>
</name>
(
<year>1976</year>
).
<article-title>Task Analysis in Instructional Design: Some Cases from Mathematics</article-title>
. In
<source>Cognition and Instruction</source>
, pp.
<fpage>51</fpage>
-
<lpage>80</lpage>
. Edited by
<name name-style="western">
<surname>David Klahr</surname>
</name>
.
<publisher-loc>Hillsdale, N. J.</publisher-loc>
:
<publisher-name>Lawrence Erlbaum Associates</publisher-name>
.</citation>
</ref>
<ref>
<citation citation-type="book" xlink:type="simple">
<name name-style="western">
<surname>Simon, H. A.</surname>
</name>
(
<year>1962</year>
).
<article-title>An Information-Processing Theory of Intellectual Development</article-title>
. In
<source>Thought in the Young Child</source>
, pp.
<fpage>137</fpage>
-
<lpage>161</lpage>
. Edited by
<name name-style="western">
<surname>William Kessen</surname>
</name>
and
<name name-style="western">
<surname>Clementina Kuhlman</surname>
</name>
. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development, Vol. 27.
<publisher-loc>Lafayette, Ind.</publisher-loc>
:
<publisher-name>Child Development Publications</publisher-name>
.</citation>
</ref>
</ref-list>
</back>
</article>
</istex:document>
</istex:metadataXml>
<mods version="3.6">
<titleInfo lang="en">
<title>Musicology and Psychomusicology: Two Sciences of Music</title>
</titleInfo>
<titleInfo type="alternative" lang="en" contentType="CDATA">
<title>Musicology and Psychomusicology: Two Sciences of Music</title>
</titleInfo>
<name type="personal">
<namePart type="given">Otto E.</namePart>
<namePart type="family">Laske</namePart>
<affiliation>University of Illinois, Urbana, IL 61801, USA.</affiliation>
</name>
<typeOfResource>text</typeOfResource>
<genre type="research-article" displayLabel="research-article" authority="ISTEX" authorityURI="https://content-type.data.istex.fr" valueURI="https://content-type.data.istex.fr/ark:/67375/XTP-1JC4F85T-7">research-article</genre>
<originInfo>
<publisher>Sage Publications</publisher>
<place>
<placeTerm type="text">Sage CA: Thousand Oaks, CA</placeTerm>
</place>
<dateIssued encoding="w3cdtf">1977-10</dateIssued>
<copyrightDate encoding="w3cdtf">1977</copyrightDate>
</originInfo>
<language>
<languageTerm type="code" authority="iso639-2b">eng</languageTerm>
<languageTerm type="code" authority="rfc3066">en</languageTerm>
</language>
<relatedItem type="host">
<titleInfo>
<title>Psychology of music</title>
</titleInfo>
<genre type="journal" authority="ISTEX" authorityURI="https://publication-type.data.istex.fr" valueURI="https://publication-type.data.istex.fr/ark:/67375/JMC-0GLKJH51-B">journal</genre>
<identifier type="ISSN">0305-7356</identifier>
<identifier type="eISSN">1741-3087</identifier>
<identifier type="PublisherID">POM</identifier>
<identifier type="PublisherID-hwp">sppom</identifier>
<part>
<date>1977</date>
<detail type="volume">
<caption>vol.</caption>
<number>5</number>
</detail>
<detail type="issue">
<caption>no.</caption>
<number>2</number>
</detail>
<extent unit="pages">
<start>10</start>
<end>22</end>
</extent>
</part>
</relatedItem>
<identifier type="istex">2CE7E3C702658579B7A1D2507D1A5A930CDD374D</identifier>
<identifier type="ark">ark:/67375/M70-9KM9MZRZ-T</identifier>
<identifier type="DOI">10.1177/030573567752002</identifier>
<identifier type="ArticleID">10.1177_030573567752002</identifier>
<recordInfo>
<recordContentSource authority="ISTEX" authorityURI="https://loaded-corpus.data.istex.fr" valueURI="https://loaded-corpus.data.istex.fr/ark:/67375/XBH-0J1N7DQT-B">sage</recordContentSource>
</recordInfo>
</mods>
<json:item>
<extension>json</extension>
<original>false</original>
<mimetype>application/json</mimetype>
<uri>https://api.istex.fr/document/2CE7E3C702658579B7A1D2507D1A5A930CDD374D/metadata/json</uri>
</json:item>
</metadata>
<serie></serie>
</istex>
</record>

Pour manipuler ce document sous Unix (Dilib)

EXPLOR_STEP=$WICRI_ROOT/Wicri/Musique/explor/XenakisV1/Data/Istex/Corpus
HfdSelect -h $EXPLOR_STEP/biblio.hfd -nk 000329 | SxmlIndent | more

Ou

HfdSelect -h $EXPLOR_AREA/Data/Istex/Corpus/biblio.hfd -nk 000329 | SxmlIndent | more

Pour mettre un lien sur cette page dans le réseau Wicri

{{Explor lien
   |wiki=    Wicri/Musique
   |area=    XenakisV1
   |flux=    Istex
   |étape=   Corpus
   |type=    RBID
   |clé=     ISTEX:2CE7E3C702658579B7A1D2507D1A5A930CDD374D
   |texte=   Musicology and Psychomusicology: Two Sciences of Music
}}

Wicri

This area was generated with Dilib version V0.6.33.
Data generation: Thu Nov 8 16:12:13 2018. Site generation: Wed Mar 6 22:10:31 2024