Serveur d'exploration Debussy

Attention, ce site est en cours de développement !
Attention, site généré par des moyens informatiques à partir de corpus bruts.
Les informations ne sont donc pas validées.

Music education freed from colonialism: a new praxis

Identifieur interne : 002167 ( Istex/Corpus ); précédent : 002166; suivant : 002168

Music education freed from colonialism: a new praxis

Auteurs : Robert Walker

Source :

RBID : ISTEX:21ED2F57E141C4FAC8AACDD069E6B548457AA513

Abstract

This paper argues against a conflation of the culturally specific (i.e. the western) and the universal in theoretical discourse about music and music education. The charge is made that music education practices generally have lost touch with the contemporary practices of musicians, thus isolating music education from other educational practices. Set in a context of ISME's commitment to a world view of music and music education, such problems are serious. It is argued that the use of western terminology is inimical to ISME's goals. Terms like 'music' and 'aesthetic' are specifically western. Epistemological links exist between an aesthetic theory and the associated musical practices, but these are not universal.

Url:
DOI: 10.1177/025576149602700102

Links to Exploration step

ISTEX:21ED2F57E141C4FAC8AACDD069E6B548457AA513

Le document en format XML

<record>
<TEI wicri:istexFullTextTei="biblStruct">
<teiHeader>
<fileDesc>
<titleStmt>
<title>Music education freed from colonialism: a new praxis</title>
<author>
<name sortKey="Walker, Robert" sort="Walker, Robert" uniqKey="Walker R" first="Robert" last="Walker">Robert Walker</name>
<affiliation>
<mods:affiliation>University of British Columbia, Vancouver, Canada</mods:affiliation>
</affiliation>
</author>
</titleStmt>
<publicationStmt>
<idno type="wicri:source">ISTEX</idno>
<idno type="RBID">ISTEX:21ED2F57E141C4FAC8AACDD069E6B548457AA513</idno>
<date when="1996" year="1996">1996</date>
<idno type="doi">10.1177/025576149602700102</idno>
<idno type="url">https://api.istex.fr/document/21ED2F57E141C4FAC8AACDD069E6B548457AA513/fulltext/pdf</idno>
<idno type="wicri:Area/Istex/Corpus">002167</idno>
<idno type="wicri:explorRef" wicri:stream="Istex" wicri:step="Corpus" wicri:corpus="ISTEX">002167</idno>
</publicationStmt>
<sourceDesc>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<title level="a">Music education freed from colonialism: a new praxis</title>
<author>
<name sortKey="Walker, Robert" sort="Walker, Robert" uniqKey="Walker R" first="Robert" last="Walker">Robert Walker</name>
<affiliation>
<mods:affiliation>University of British Columbia, Vancouver, Canada</mods:affiliation>
</affiliation>
</author>
</analytic>
<monogr></monogr>
<series>
<title level="j">International Journal of Music Education</title>
<idno type="ISSN">0255-7614</idno>
<imprint>
<publisher>Sage Publications</publisher>
<pubPlace>Sage CA: Thousand Oaks, CA</pubPlace>
<date type="published" when="1996">1996</date>
<biblScope unit="volume">27</biblScope>
<biblScope unit="issue">1</biblScope>
<biblScope unit="page" from="2">2</biblScope>
<biblScope unit="page" to="15">15</biblScope>
</imprint>
<idno type="ISSN">0255-7614</idno>
</series>
</biblStruct>
</sourceDesc>
<seriesStmt>
<idno type="ISSN">0255-7614</idno>
</seriesStmt>
</fileDesc>
<profileDesc>
<textClass></textClass>
</profileDesc>
</teiHeader>
<front>
<div type="abstract">This paper argues against a conflation of the culturally specific (i.e. the western) and the universal in theoretical discourse about music and music education. The charge is made that music education practices generally have lost touch with the contemporary practices of musicians, thus isolating music education from other educational practices. Set in a context of ISME's commitment to a world view of music and music education, such problems are serious. It is argued that the use of western terminology is inimical to ISME's goals. Terms like 'music' and 'aesthetic' are specifically western. Epistemological links exist between an aesthetic theory and the associated musical practices, but these are not universal.</div>
</front>
</TEI>
<istex>
<corpusName>sage</corpusName>
<author>
<json:item>
<name>Robert Walker</name>
<affiliations>
<json:string>University of British Columbia, Vancouver, Canada</json:string>
</affiliations>
</json:item>
</author>
<arkIstex>ark:/67375/M70-NSW663Q1-0</arkIstex>
<language>
<json:string>unknown</json:string>
</language>
<originalGenre>
<json:string>Journal Article</json:string>
</originalGenre>
<abstract>This paper argues against a conflation of the culturally specific (i.e. the western) and the universal in theoretical discourse about music and music education. The charge is made that music education practices generally have lost touch with the contemporary practices of musicians, thus isolating music education from other educational practices. Set in a context of ISME's commitment to a world view of music and music education, such problems are serious. It is argued that the use of western terminology is inimical to ISME's goals. Terms like 'music' and 'aesthetic' are specifically western. Epistemological links exist between an aesthetic theory and the associated musical practices, but these are not universal.</abstract>
<qualityIndicators>
<score>8.308</score>
<pdfWordCount>6164</pdfWordCount>
<pdfCharCount>36666</pdfCharCount>
<pdfVersion>1.4</pdfVersion>
<pdfPageCount>14</pdfPageCount>
<pdfPageSize>612 x 792 pts (letter)</pdfPageSize>
<refBibsNative>true</refBibsNative>
<abstractWordCount>109</abstractWordCount>
<abstractCharCount>720</abstractCharCount>
<keywordCount>0</keywordCount>
</qualityIndicators>
<title>Music education freed from colonialism: a new praxis</title>
<genre>
<json:string>research-article</json:string>
</genre>
<host>
<title>International Journal of Music Education</title>
<language>
<json:string>unknown</json:string>
</language>
<issn>
<json:string>0255-7614</json:string>
</issn>
<volume>27</volume>
<issue>1</issue>
<pages>
<first>2</first>
<last>15</last>
</pages>
<genre>
<json:string>journal</json:string>
</genre>
</host>
<ark>
<json:string>ark:/67375/M70-NSW663Q1-0</json:string>
</ark>
<categories>
<wos>
<json:string>1 - social science</json:string>
<json:string>2 - education & educational research</json:string>
</wos>
<scienceMetrix>
<json:string>1 - arts & humanities</json:string>
<json:string>2 - visual & performing arts</json:string>
<json:string>3 - music</json:string>
</scienceMetrix>
<scopus>
<json:string>1 - Social Sciences</json:string>
<json:string>2 - Arts and Humanities</json:string>
<json:string>3 - Music</json:string>
<json:string>1 - Social Sciences</json:string>
<json:string>2 - Social Sciences</json:string>
<json:string>3 - Education</json:string>
</scopus>
<inist>
<json:string>1 - sciences humaines et sociales</json:string>
</inist>
</categories>
<publicationDate>1996</publicationDate>
<copyrightDate>1996</copyrightDate>
<doi>
<json:string>10.1177/025576149602700102</json:string>
</doi>
<id>21ED2F57E141C4FAC8AACDD069E6B548457AA513</id>
<score>1</score>
<fulltext>
<json:item>
<extension>pdf</extension>
<original>true</original>
<mimetype>application/pdf</mimetype>
<uri>https://api.istex.fr/document/21ED2F57E141C4FAC8AACDD069E6B548457AA513/fulltext/pdf</uri>
</json:item>
<json:item>
<extension>zip</extension>
<original>false</original>
<mimetype>application/zip</mimetype>
<uri>https://api.istex.fr/document/21ED2F57E141C4FAC8AACDD069E6B548457AA513/fulltext/zip</uri>
</json:item>
<istex:fulltextTEI uri="https://api.istex.fr/document/21ED2F57E141C4FAC8AACDD069E6B548457AA513/fulltext/tei">
<teiHeader>
<fileDesc>
<titleStmt>
<title level="a">Music education freed from colonialism: a new praxis</title>
</titleStmt>
<publicationStmt>
<authority>ISTEX</authority>
<publisher scheme="https://publisher-list.data.istex.fr">Sage Publications</publisher>
<pubPlace>Sage CA: Thousand Oaks, CA</pubPlace>
<availability>
<licence>
<p>sage</p>
</licence>
</availability>
<p scheme="https://loaded-corpus.data.istex.fr/ark:/67375/XBH-0J1N7DQT-B"></p>
<date>1996</date>
</publicationStmt>
<notesStmt>
<note type="research-article" scheme="https://content-type.data.istex.fr/ark:/67375/XTP-1JC4F85T-7">research-article</note>
<note type="journal" scheme="https://publication-type.data.istex.fr/ark:/67375/JMC-0GLKJH51-B">journal</note>
</notesStmt>
<sourceDesc>
<biblStruct type="inbook">
<analytic>
<title level="a">Music education freed from colonialism: a new praxis</title>
<author xml:id="author-0000">
<persName>
<forename type="first">Robert</forename>
<surname>Walker</surname>
</persName>
<affiliation>University of British Columbia, Vancouver, Canada</affiliation>
</author>
<idno type="istex">21ED2F57E141C4FAC8AACDD069E6B548457AA513</idno>
<idno type="ark">ark:/67375/M70-NSW663Q1-0</idno>
<idno type="DOI">10.1177/025576149602700102</idno>
</analytic>
<monogr>
<title level="j">International Journal of Music Education</title>
<idno type="pISSN">0255-7614</idno>
<imprint>
<publisher>Sage Publications</publisher>
<pubPlace>Sage CA: Thousand Oaks, CA</pubPlace>
<date type="published" when="1996"></date>
<biblScope unit="volume">27</biblScope>
<biblScope unit="issue">1</biblScope>
<biblScope unit="page" from="2">2</biblScope>
<biblScope unit="page" to="15">15</biblScope>
</imprint>
</monogr>
</biblStruct>
</sourceDesc>
</fileDesc>
<profileDesc>
<creation>
<date>1996</date>
</creation>
<abstract>
<p>This paper argues against a conflation of the culturally specific (i.e. the western) and the universal in theoretical discourse about music and music education. The charge is made that music education practices generally have lost touch with the contemporary practices of musicians, thus isolating music education from other educational practices. Set in a context of ISME's commitment to a world view of music and music education, such problems are serious. It is argued that the use of western terminology is inimical to ISME's goals. Terms like 'music' and 'aesthetic' are specifically western. Epistemological links exist between an aesthetic theory and the associated musical practices, but these are not universal.</p>
</abstract>
</profileDesc>
<revisionDesc>
<change when="1996">Published</change>
</revisionDesc>
</teiHeader>
</istex:fulltextTEI>
<json:item>
<extension>txt</extension>
<original>false</original>
<mimetype>text/plain</mimetype>
<uri>https://api.istex.fr/document/21ED2F57E141C4FAC8AACDD069E6B548457AA513/fulltext/txt</uri>
</json:item>
</fulltext>
<metadata>
<istex:metadataXml wicri:clean="corpus sage not found" wicri:toSee="no header">
<istex:xmlDeclaration>version="1.0" encoding="ISO-8859-1"</istex:xmlDeclaration>
<istex:docType SYSTEM="SAGE_meta.dtd" name="istex:docType"></istex:docType>
<istex:document>
<SAGEmeta type="Journal Article" doi="10.1177/025576149602700102">
<header>
<jrn_info>
<jrn_title>International Journal of Music Education</jrn_title>
<ISSN>0255-7614</ISSN>
<vol>27</vol>
<iss>1</iss>
<date>
<yy>1996</yy>
<mm></mm>
</date>
<pub_info>
<pub_name>Sage Publications</pub_name>
<pub_location>Sage CA: Thousand Oaks, CA</pub_location>
</pub_info>
</jrn_info>
<art_info>
<art_title>Music education freed from colonialism: a new praxis</art_title>
<art_author>
<per_aut>
<fn>Robert</fn>
<ln>Walker</ln>
<affil>University of British Columbia, Vancouver, Canada</affil>
</per_aut>
</art_author>
<spn>2</spn>
<epn>15</epn>
<descriptors></descriptors>
</art_info>
</header>
<body>
<abstract>
<p>This paper argues against a conflation of the culturally specific (i.e. the western) and the universal in theoretical discourse about music and music education. The charge is made that music education practices generally have lost touch with the contemporary practices of musicians, thus isolating music education from other educational practices. Set in a context of ISME's commitment to a world view of music and music education, such problems are serious. It is argued that the use of western terminology is inimical to ISME's goals. Terms like 'music' and 'aesthetic' are specifically western. Epistemological links exist between an aesthetic theory and the associated musical practices, but these are not universal.</p>
</abstract>
<full_text>2 Music education freed from colonialism: a new praxis SAGE Publications, Inc.1996DOI: 10.1177/025576149602700102 Robert Walker University of British Columbia, Vancouver, Canada This paper argues against a conflation of the culturally specific (i.e. the western) and the universal in theoretical discourse about music and music education. The charge is made that music education practices generally have lost touch with the contemporary practices of musicians, thus isolating music education from other educational practices. Set in a context of ISME's commitment to a world view of music and music education, such problems are serious. It is argued that the use of western terminology is inimical to ISME's goals. Terms like 'music' and 'aesthetic' are specifically western. Epistemological links exist between an aesthetic theory and the associated musical practices, but these are not universal. Elliott (1994) claims that 'progress' has rendered Music Education as Aesthetic Education (MEAE) no more than a 'net-work of obsolete claims'. He suggests that we need to 'design a logical blueprint for investigating the concept of ~usi~...'. In support of his claim for a need to develop his 'blueprint' he links together some disparate sources in explaining the nature of the obsolescence ofMEAE, some of which makes for a questionable starting point for his design. It is quite surprising, for example, that anyone would seriously link Swanwick's views with those of Reimer. But most surprising of all is his statement that the value of aesthetic education 'as a philosophy is wrong-headed'. In his attempt at producing a definition tabula rash he describes music as 'intentional human activity, involving a doer, a maker, a product and a context'. Thus, we have a definition for anything humans do, ranging from mowing the lawn to cooking, dress-making, making love, or catching fish. Elliott then produces the following terminology; doers (musicers); doing (music;iya~)9 something done (music); and context. He claims that music can be looked at in four ways: (a) head-on, the outcome of systematic action; (b) in-back, motivated, action; (c) in-front, goal-orientated action; (d) action in the context of similar actions. Not only does this take us no further from any kind of behaviour in which humans indulge but it reads as if (d) was to get rich quick on the stock market. We still do not know what music is, and even as a beginning such value definitions are surely redundant. The problem I see with Elliott's position, albeit not a philosophy but the establishment of 'logically prior conditions' to one, is that he falls into the same pigeon-hole that he claims Langer and all who followed 3 her fell into - a desire for establishing universal principles from diverse particulars which may be incommensurate. In doing so he raises the same issues that Nietzsche dealt with, and in particular Nietzsche's claim that 'the aesthetic is applied physiology' is relevant. The western concern for establishing whether or not there are universally applicable correlates between specific musical sounds and specific responses has been matched in music education by a concern for an all-embracing philosophy of music education. Either quest is probably fruitless since music, like language, and everything else humans do, is rooted in culture. The issue is not that music is a human activity, but that humans operate within socio-cultural systems of which music is only a part. The autonomous musical sound does not exist, and Neitzsche and all who followed him provide a more appropriate philosophical pigeon-hole, if we need one. The gist of my argument here concerns the significance of the claim that musicians provide the best source of musical information relevant to music educators, and that perhaps we do not need a philosophy of music education at all, since music education (similarly not autonomous) operates within systems which have an overall philosophy of education. However, I have to clear some ground first. Changing social, political, economic, technical and other considerations mark western history. So the first issue concerns a discussion of aesthetic education on logical rather than socio-cultural grounds. There is nothing inherently illogical in the concept of aesthetic education as music education. What is problematic is its contemporary efficacy and relevance, which is a differcnt mattcr entirely. But more fundamental than this are teleological issues concerning the nature and purpose of music in relation to various socio-cultural situations and hypotheses about consequent human responses to music. No system universally relating properties of culturally embedded sounds with the biology of the human nervous system has been identified which might explain aesthetic experience, or any similar complex human response. Responses and the sounds which are associated with them seem to be as varied as socio-cultural conditions, and the efforts of Helmholtz, Wundt and all who followed in their traditions have produced little which might explain human responses to music purely in terms of acoustic-biological interactions. Anthropological paradigms seem to be our most reliable means of enquiry and source of understanding in music. This brings its own problems, not the least among which concerns terminology and its significance. Terminological usage arises out of socio-cultural conditions, and in order to understand the significance of terms such as 'aesthetic experience' or 'music' one cannot avoid examining their socio-cultural embedding. And using words arising out of one socio-cultural situation in the context of another inevitably causes difficulties. E AE ~ `I'IC E E ENC IS A C IJCIAL PART F WESTERN VULTURE Modern arguments concerning the 'aesthetic' began in the 18th century, but 'aesthetic' music linked with the full-blown modern German theory 4 did not emerge until the 19th century Central Europe of the 18th century had its own musical fads and accompanying literature: the 'Doctrine of the Affections'; notions of 'elegance' and 'psychic distance' (see Anderson, 1938); the 'Sturm und Drang'. These are attributes which are as different in subtle ways from the igth century German notion of the ,aesthetic' as is the music of J. S. Bach, Haydn and Mozart from that of Liszt, Schumann and Brahnis. The Rome of the early 16th century had 'mannerism' and the concept of 'sprezzatura', defined and demonstrated by Castiglione (1528) and involving Michelangelo and Rafael, all of whom provided the background for the development of the young Palestrina. One could go on and on with a catalogue of different viewpoints and fashions found throughout modern western artistic history, each with its own special terminology. The term 'aesthetic' appeared first in the literary theory of 18th century German with Baumgarten (1750). The aesthetic in music is but one of these 'fashions' which emerged in the 19th century but lives on in western culture. It is however a well thought-out concept which has a logic based in musical structure of composers such as Beethoven, Liszt, Schunann, Brahms and Wagner, and argued in the texts of Hegel, Schopenhauer, Hanslick, Fichte, Schellin and Schlegel. The music written to this specific theory of aesthetic experience consti- tutes a supreme expression of the culture of central Europe in the 19th century. Philosophically, this 19th century German position moved the locus of debate about aesthetic experience from issues of sense perception and feelings to those of transcendental experiences of pure beauty and perfection. This shift was controversial at the time, and philosophers of the English analytic traditions argued bitterly against it. It is puzzling that this controversy still lives on in music education literature where 19th century German transcendentalism is often confused or conflated with the more pragmatic, analytic examination of sense perception and its probable connection with feelings. Discussions in this latter field have few connections with the art of music, and for the most part remain in the realm of speculative argument with little if any practical application in music. In contrast, the specific 19th century German aesthetic tradition has powerful identity in actual music. My point is that the 19th century German notion of the aesthetic in music is not like an incomplete or spurious philosophical or scientific notion to be superseded as knowledge increases or analytical method becomes more sophisticated. It constitutes a powerful cultural artefact. It is not, for example, like the 19th century search for isomorphic relationships between physical attributes and ability or character. The 19th century had such things in abundance: human intelligence was thought to be linked to head size as in the empirical theory of craniology; and noble art in all its manifestations was thought to be produced by noble people, hence the rise of the artist hero. We can justifiably argue that such things are illogical. On the other hand, from its cultural embedding as an interactive philosophical and artistic concept, the efficacy of this particular view of aesthetic experience has enabled it to spread to survive. Modern versions of this 19th century German musical praxis are found 5 today in various entertainment media. Many Hollywood films evoke this particular aesthetic response with their igth century style drama and music. The clever pastiche of John William in writing music for so many films which enjoyed world-wide popularity over the last two decades ~6Ja~rs', 'E.T.', 'Raiders of the Lost Ark' or the 'Star Wars Trilogy'9 for example) has helped introduce and perhaps redefine the concept to the world. This German aesthetic concept is, therefore, an important part of our contemporary, media-dominated, popular world culture, raising many issues to do with its relevance today in education. It may not be that irrelevant to some, even though they may not realize its debt to 19th century Germany! Above all it should be distinguished from non- contextual and generic analytical debates on aesthetic sense perception by virtue of its close association with artistic, culturally rooted products. WESTERN 9 h4USlC AND AESTHETIC EXPERIENCE One difficulty western philosophy has always had with artistic fashions is to do with how such things fit with concepts such as universalism, pluralism or relativism. Is there something universal about all musical fads and fashions which unites the musical products under one umbrella which can define and delineate music, qua music, or are we talking of relative values, or of pluralist values? A rampant relativism gives value to everything which, logically, means that nothing is valuable. One would expect proponents of aesthetic education to be concerned with aesthetic values which are at least pluralistic, if not universal, But if the reference is to supposed autonomous qualities of sound which elicit, through some generic human process, an aesthetic response in all humans, then it can have no specific connection with the art of music as it subsists in human lives, for this would be specific and concern particulars. For music educators, as opposed to philosophers, it is the specifics, the particulars of human activities which matter more than theoretical and untestable ideas about generic human response mechanisms. A specific aesthetic theory linked with specific musical practices existed in central Europe during the 19th century, and this provides specific educational focus for music educators dealing with aesthetic experience. A lack of specific musical connections with a general philosophical theory about aesthetic sensibilities of humans is unhelpful to educators for it leaves them with nothing to teach about music. Even more damaging to the art of music would be an educational application which assumed a generic aesthetic response in students devoid of socio-cultural embedding. There would be nothing for students to learn about themselves, or about other people in other situations, for the concern could go no further than speculations about the mechanics of acoustic-biological interactions. My point here is that 'aesthetic experience in music' should not be regarded as a generic mechanical universal: the term should refer to particular cultural artifacts. Detailed studies of the history of ideas and their influence over various musical practices in the West would surely illustrate the concept of plurality rather than universality. L6onin, 106 Pérotin, Josquin or Machaut did not have 'aesthetic' considerations nor experiences in their music-making. Unless, that is, one subscribes to the view that western consciousness follows a linear development of ever more penetrating understanding of the truth. In which case L6onin did have aesthetic experiences but did not know it at the time. There is more than a bit of arrogance in that view, but here is the crux of the problem. If an aesthetic nature is endemic to all humans, then identifying its defining qualities obviously concerns universals, and one must regard such philosophers as Kant, Schopenhauer, Hegel, as lifting the veils obscuring universal human truth, despite what musicians did. But without a direct connection with the practices of music we have nothing to teach except an abstract, decontextualised philosophy. On the other hand, if the focus is a specific, culturally rooted aesthetic sense articulated as such by some and practised as such by musicians ~g.e. the 19th century German example) then we should treat it as a cultural artefact, and treasure it as one of many aesthetic pluralities. Its continued presence today cannot be taken as evidence of a universal human aesthetic response. The most that essentialists might claim out of its continued presence is that it breathes life into the otherwise musically lifeless framework of a notion of generic human aesthetic sensibilities. Others would merely point to how today's technology facilitates the juxtaposition of the historical with the contemporary to form the complex of experiences which some label 'post-modern', and our affective responses to music, like anything else, are a product of our enculturation in today's world. But no acculturation is value neutral, and values emanate from socio-cultural roots, not biology. Just as different traditions within western culture supported different theories and perceptions (many of which we are still arguing about - the mind-body problem, for example), different cultures also support differences emanating from their socio-economic, technological, geographical, and many other conditional factors. Do we regard these differences as pluralities or relativities? As pluralities, cultures hold their own values but unite with others in having values, even if they are sometimes divergent. Moreover, such pluralist values have individual integrity where each relates to its own moral purposes and provides stability for the people of the culture. So we would go for plurality over relativity in both inter- and intra-cultural situations; it makes more moral sense to us. But what does it mean in practice cross-culturally? It means, I suggest, accepting sounds from a culture other than our own, not necessarily as music in the western sense, but as cultural expressions which only have significance in the special terms of their cultural embedding: the types of throat singing of the Inuit or the Tuvinians, for example, are different in this way from each other and from the 19th century romantic lied. Each has value in our pluralist universe, but of what help is this claim? Try as we may, to a westerner throat-singing does not sound like music as a westerner knows it. So, I suggest, let us accept this and tackle the problem differently. Perhaps throat-singing is not music since, as I argue below, 'music' is a term developed specifically in the West to signify modern western practices. The sounds of both lied 117 and throat-singing emanate from the vocal tract, but each requires a different use of vocal articulators and the respiratory system, which in turn produces different physical events. Since each has its own cultural embedding and special physical attributes, why should they be labelled identically? °I'E ~ ®~ G~ A CIJLTURAL RELEVANCY We in the West talk of music, art and the aesthetic. Few other cultures have words for such things. For the people of Ball, for example, there is no word for art or music in their language any more than there is in the languages of many North American Indian peoples or Australian Aborigines. If a culture has no word f®r music, for example, then logically it follows that it has no concept of music. Most cultures use music in trance or possession rituals (Rouget, 1985), but to equate this with the western 19th century aesthetic response would be a distortion of both. Moving further down this road, we can claim to have no good reason for including non-western activities which we think of wrongly as 'musiccal' or 'aesthetic' in our pedagogies which seek to educate in music. We can argue, therefore, that it is illogical to include such activities in an implied terminological umbrella or pluralities such as 'musics' or 'musicing'. It is rather like including apples, oranges, carrots and potatoes as examples of fruits or fruitings. We would certainly put all of them under the generic term 'food', but the term 'music', my argument goes, is comparable with the term 'fruit' in this respect, not the term 'food'. Here we can apply the logic of pluralism to mean a pluralism of terms and therefore concepts, not a single term to signify a pluralism of concepts. But let me explore this further. We in the West have developed the concept 'music', the Greek origins of which lie in mousike - a term originally signifying the activities of the All of them, gods and goddesses of such arts as dance, poetry, drama and singing, but in post- classical times the Latin term musica was used to signify mathematical and metaphysical ideas rather than what we now think of as 'music' (Wellesz, 1957, p. 340), its anglicised version. Later, the term came to be used to denote singing, and then instrumental music as this developed. Other cultures have different epistemologies and terminologies for their different activities in expressing their cultural systems and beliefs, yet we in the West have a habit of making everything fit our terminology and our concepts. The ubiquitous gamelan of Bali is thought by westerners to be 'musical', presumably because it appears to have the modern western 'musical' attributes of pitch, rhythm, counterpoint, and other sonic organizations with which we in the West are familiar. Interestingly enough, Debussy heard a gamelan and then went on to produce music which many at the time labelled anti-music. Perhaps they were right: Debussy did indeed, through `~cu~~' and other works, signal the destruction of what then was taken for granted as 'music' in western Europe. But we should not forget the similar reaction in 1902 to Schoenberg's 'Transfigured Night', and he was merely taking Wagnerian compositional logic a stage further towards a language of dissonance - 128 a very western type of intellectual activity in music. So, whether as a result of contact with non-western sources or as products of the West's obsession with intellectualism, western music has seen many changes: from monody to polyphony, from vocal to instrumental, from diatonic to chromatic, from a language of consonance to one of dissonance, and so on. Within this dynamic process the term 'music' acquired its significance. In Balinese culture the term 'gamelan' does not signify similar dynamic processes of change and shining emphasis; it signifies specific activities each with its own terminology peculiar to a particular village community. There is no one thing called a gamelan And it is essentially a collection of instruments of ritual, not of concerts, as integral to the particular socio-cultural imperatives of Balinese Hindu beliefs as are Balinese puppet dancing or vocal declamations in their performances of the `I~a~ayarra' stories. There are at least two grounds on which one might claim that 'gamelan' does not signify music in the western sense: acoustic and social. First, the acoustic properties of the gamelan's metal bars and gongs do not yield sufficient pitch information for western musical purposes. A gamelan version of a Mozart piano sonata would work as badly as a piano version of gainelan sounds for a sarong drama. The fact that western ears can 'impose' pitch on most quasi-periodic sounds does not make them all music by western definition. Second, because of the importance attached to cultural embedding, it is as inappropriate to extract gamelan sounds from their context and significance in order to call them 'music' as it would be to extract Balinese vocalisations and call therra `poctr°y' or the physical movements of the Sarong and call them 'ballet'. By what right, then, or by what logic, do we extricate the gamelan from its life- giving socio-cultural context to make it part of a pluralist western set of activities we call `rrmsic'? Well, let me explore this further. And though to recording company moguls or media tycoons, whose influence over our students is enviable, all this might seem excessively trivial, and certainly irrelevant to their interests, I bask in the belief that to educators it does not and should not. 9 A WESTERN TERM FOR A PARTICULAR WESTERN CULTURAL ACTIVITY If my arguments so far hold water, in trying to establish a universal term we are obliged to descend to such a level of ambiguity of definition in order to accommodate 'musics' from outside the western traditions that we are left with a description of activity which covers practically everything humans do. In which case, like all such rlotiorrs, it hardly avoids the relativistic trap of lack of clear delineation if applied universally. But it also renders the term 'music', as it defines modern western activities, meaningless. The term 'music' is as culturally laden with western traditions of the last several hundred years as is the term 'gamelan' with Balinese traditions. Perhaps John Cage (1939) had a point in suggesting that 'music' is a term 'reserved for 18th and 19th century (European) instruments', even though we might want to spread the net a bit further 139 than that. But first, some ideas from contemporary philosophy, particularly relating to language and meaning. It was Herder and Hegel who focused attention on the importance of culture in determining our sense of identity and our understanding and interpretation of phenomena. And it was the revival of Hegel in post- Second World War France which helped spawn the post-structuralist movement through the writings of Foucault, Merlot-Ponty, Derridas, Barthes and others. Michael Foucault (1966) argued for a view of language in which meaning was derived not just from cultural embedding but also from an individual's own personal origins and context. Thus there was nothing inherently authoritarian, for example, or noble in any per- son's speech or writings, that is to say in the words that they used or their manner of delivery. Such specific attributes could only be perceived by those who shared and accepted the same cultural value systems. Words had meanings which were negotiable outside their particular socio-cultural setting, not inherent, argued Foucault. These ideas found their way into various media quite quickly. Television comedy actors like those of the Monty Python group during the 1970s demonstrated that English authoritarian mannerisms could very easily become risible, even objects of derision when placed outside their socio-cultural context, thus destroying the notion that there was anything inherently authoritarian in either a particular mode of delivery or the words used. These developments challenged essentialist assumptions about language, meaning and usage. 61D'~&ds~~a~, as a term, becomes, like 'democracy', simply a western word struggling for identity in a pluralist, post-modern world. Etymologically, I have argued above that there is little justification for the expansion of the western term 'music' outside of western traditions. Educationally, a great deal of confusion (and probably unintended cultural imperialism) could be avoided by a classification based more on socio-cultural embedding than on old colonial appropriations, and acoustic properties might be key here. The essence of music, qua music, as historically defined in western thought, concerns pitch, unambiguously periodic sounds rich in stable harmonics and therefore susceptible to combinations in western practices of harmony and counterpoint. Dissonance, in western musical terms, refers to deviations from such harmonic norms. We cannot fit sounds from outside western traditions into such a paradigm without insulting and destroying their integrity, as well as implying that we in the West have developed the art of music to higher degrees of sophistication than others because of our technology and culture. But such a definition also causes problems for the musical avant-garde of the 20th century, a point I have already mentioned and to which I return later. Post-modern thought suggests a re-evaluation of both terminological signification and usage on both logical and socio-political grounds. In such things, the universal use of the term 'music' means either we reject its connection with western musical theory through processes of semantic deconstruction, in which case its products become conceptually indistinguishable from sonic activities of other cultures, or we paternist- ically bring these activities into the fold of music with all the built-in 1410 sense of superiority that involves. This makes as much, or as little, sense as adopting a term from any other culture to use universally. Why not, for example, use the Ghanaian word dwom (pronounced jom), for example, as a universal term instead of 'music', since it signifies the use of the voice in social activities we might classify as dance, games or theatre? Or the Ghanaian term agror, a collective noun signifying a complex of cultural activities involving movement, drama, words, actions, vocalisations? Such a solution might well be more universally democratic since such terms have no connotations of a dominant world culture. But western scholars would surely object on the grounds that a concept, signified by a word, is produced over time as a result of social usage and is linked inextricably with the activities it signifies. l~bsolutcly! Certain specific Ghanaian practices are signified by the word dwom. So why should the Ghanaians want to use our western word music to signify dwom, any more than western musicians would want to use dwom to signify what the West calls music? CAN MUSIC EDUCATION GO NOW? Where does all this leave us in music education? Well, to begin with, if aesthetic experience in music is essentially socio-cultural and context specific we must teach it as such, not treat it either as a worn-out bicycle or part of some cosmic search for truth. But we cannot rely just on the sounds of music: we should know the philosophical arguments and provide some experiences which can induce aesthetic responses (such as in Hollywood films for example). And if pitch is an acoustic attribute specially defined in the West it is a degrading acoustic identity for the sounds of other cultures which may be quasi-periodic but where pitch extraction may be epiphenomenal in their cultural practices. Most importantly, if we cannot rely on the term 'music' as a universal, the we cannot rely on the concept of music education if we wish to go outside the music, qua music, of the western traditions. This suggests making some choices in our quest to define a global policy for what we now call music education. Either we limit our concept of music and music education to the western traditions, and we find another term which would enable us to include activities of other cultures however defined, or we continue to assume that all cultures make what we in the West have defined as music. I do not think it is viable or logical to use the term 'musics' as though we all know what it means. Basically, it is only we in the West who know what it means. There are, however, consequences for world music education with the abandonment of the term `n~uslc'. If we cannot use the term 'music' on grounds that it would ignore the crucial acoustic differences and the socio-cultural embedding of the activities we wish to utilize, then we would have music education for western music plus some other activity in the curriculum which concerned other cultures. In which case, and at the very least, this latter ought to be concerned with a scientific study of acoustic properties in order to escape the trap of assuming universal usage of western concepts. Additionally, we would need a more holistic 1511 socio-cultural involvement with all that goes to make up a particular lifestyle. But then we are faced with a problem over western music. Can we justify teaching western music as an autonomous sonic object (the 19th century belief associated with the German Aesthetic) removed from its socio-cultural context, yet at the same time teaching differently, as socio-cultural phenomena, the activities we think are nearest to our western concept of music found in other cultures? No! I would answer. We should recognize them all as socio-cultural acoustic phenomena even if it means placing 19th century beliefs into the pluralists' bag, despite the historical belief in universal properties. A PRAXIS I suggest that the revolution we might seek in music education lics less in seeking clearer generic definitions in a quest for philosophical clarity, since in the Wittgenstinian sense philosophy itself is no less of a cultural artefact that music, and more in identifying the purposes of education in music in the western traditions and similar activities in other cultures. I do acknowledge, however, that in writing this paper I rely on the possibility of a universal analytical approach which must be our only hope for developing world understanding. For example, we should revisit the thorny old issue of why we are teaching music at all, and why we should teach what some erroneously label 'musics' of all cultures. Pragmatically, there are probably two main justifications: to train a few people to be professional musicians, and to educate everyone to understand the practices we call 'music' and other activities in different cultures so that there is some point to being a professional performer in our post-modern, media-dominated world (there might be an audience!). Educationally, I argue that regarding doom, gamelan, as socio-cultural acoustic phenomena, rather than autonomous transcultural sonic materials, provides a more solid basis for arguments about educational justification. All human activities in all cultures arise out of the technological, biological and socio-cultural details of everyday living, much like plants and animals arise out of the physical and biological conditions here on the planet earth. Each in our own culture develops beliefs, rituals and other special cultural habits, and included among these, inextricably and ineluctably, is this activity we in the West call music, or Ghanaians call doom. Empirically, one can claim that this is what happens in all human societies. If we hold that an education should contain studies of humans in different societies and times in order, at the very least, to develop understanding of our own predicament and how we might relate to those of others' predicaments, then to leave out of such studies activities like music and dwom would be tantamount to ignoring some of the most significant and meaningful activities humans indulge in. This position is only tenable if we accept music and dwom as socio-cultural phenomena, rooted in culture and uniquely reflective and expressive of the culture. In which case, if we leave music out of education we would not be talking about a study of humans in societies which had justifiable 1612 claims to educational completeness. It is not just that all human societies use sound as communication but rather such usage is a crucial and integral part of what that society is all about. To ignore these activities, however defined, is to ignore important information about the society and its individuals. This has major implications for all that we currently do in the name of 'music education for everyone', including the roles of skill acquisition and its development, performance, listening, composing, improvising and contextual studies, It necessitates an approach from a team of experts who can supply information and experiences from the variety of areas of knowledge, including technology, beliefs, socio-religious practices and rites, all of which go to make up what we know about a culture. There would be no reliance on an essentialist notion of the autonomous, culturally transcendent, generically expressive qualities of sound matched by a generic human aesthetic response to such sounds. Teaching in such a pedagogical context becomes something quite different from what we know in today's music class. The purposes of such an educational process become qualitatively different. Skill acquisition, for example, would need a socio-cultural context as an educational justification for its inclusion. There would be no educational point in training children to sing like the choristers of King's College, Cambridge, without King's College Chapel, Cambridge, and its rituals and beliefs. And the Balinese `IZarrrayar~a9 vocal declamations would be as out of place in I~in~gs College chapel as would the sounds of I~in~'s choristers singing in a Balinese ritual drama. Operationally, the solution, I suggest, lies in the following: (a) revise the content of music education from kindergarten upwards to bring it more into line with the actual activities and theoretical motivations of musicians in the 20th century; (b) make greater use of digital technology. Concerning the first, the 20th century is nearly over, yet the bulk of the content in our music education programmes at all levels is more appropriate to Mendelssohn than Nlessi~e~9 and Puccini than Par. Schools, for example, still use 19th century French time names and the 6rrr°' interval or the minor third. It is as though the 20th century never happened in music. Yet each generation in this century has produced startling innovation in musical art: i7ebussy, Stravinsky, Cowell, Ives, Webern, Schoenberg and early liar6se up to 1930; Bart6k, early Messiaeii and Cage in the 1930s and 1940s; Stockhausen, Boulez, Zenakis, Berio, Penderecki and Cage again in the 1950s and 1960s; then came Murray Schaffer, Reich, Glass and latterly Judith Weir, John Taverner, Arvo Part, to name just a few. And these do not even include the developments in jazz, blues, rock and roll and popular music fashions. It is extraordinary that music education in schools generally continues to be virtually oblivious to what has happened in the 20th century, and there is a wealth of information about the cultural embedding of these activities. Of particular significance to my argument is the fact that the work of many 20th century musicians has been greatly influenced by non-western ideas and practices. The reaction of some who labelled this new music 'anti-music' is both testimony to a recognition of the presence of non- 1713 western influences, and a compelling reason for its pedagogical use as a bridge between traditional western concepts of music and activities of other cultures. Therefore, I argue, in any attempt to address the concept of world practices in what we call music education, the most obvious pathway is to use the work of the many musicians who have assimilated some world practices into their own work and proceed from there: Cage was influenced by Zen and gamelan, Stockhausen by Japanese gagaku, Reich by the gamelan, Messiaen by bird calls, Bartok by indigenous music, and so on. The activities of many 20th century musicians, both in the West and in countries like Japan with the work of Takemitsu, provide as good a platform for music educators to launch a truly cosmopohtan approach as one can find. Suggestions for the use of 20th century practices in pedagogy are not new, of course (see Walker, 1984 and 1990). They were first tried in the late 1950s and 1960s by many teachers unheralded and practising induependently. Various publications reflecting this individual work eventually appeared: in the UK (Self, Painter, Dennis); in the 1J~~ (The Contemporary Music Project; Manhattanville Music Curriculum Project); in Canada (R. Murray Schaffer); in German (Gertrudt I~ldsy~r-Dea~k~arla~). All this activity foundered largely because the bulk of music educators had no experience of contemporary music; their own backgrounds were so rooted in the past that they had no connection with the sources of such ideas and practices. This was a great pity, and delineates one of the major educational distinctions between visual art pedagogy on the one hand, and music pedagogy on the other. Since the early 1930s visual art pedagogy has developed hand in hand with contemporary practising artists in a way that did not occur in music. While Klee, Kandinsky, Picasso, Rauschenberg, Henry Moore and Jackson Pollock, to name a few, were inspiring, and becoming models for, the art work done in school classrooms by children of all ages, music educators began a child's music education rooted in the musical concepts and constructs of the 18the century. The very recent growth and developments of digital technology has brought a new player on the scene in all aspects of education. For'music', 'dwom', or whatever term we use, it is likely that this might provide art opportunity to make a leap over several generations of music curriculum stagnation. But this will only occur if music educators make their music content commensurate with what musicians are actually doing now. Pedagogically, we should strive to be both 'where musicians are' and 'where children are' (to use slogans). Such an approach drives the content and curricula design of most other subjects in schools. In language education, for example, current practices do not advocate starting with stylised 18th century English. To say the very least about pedagogical sophistication in language education, children study language starting from their own usage, and go on to develop understanding and appreciation of the language use of others, including other times and places and eventually the works of masters of language. There is no reason why music pedagogy must proceed in the opposite direction. A new pedagogy for all students rooted in the 20th century and leading 1814 to other times, places and cultures, utilizing digital technology in the form of acoustic synthesis, sequencing, CD ROM and 'on-line' access to the vast store of examples and information available world-wide is, I suggest, the only way forward. But the lead must come from the universities and music colleges, otherwise the schools will face the uncomfortable situation of square pegs, that is to say music educators with historical and pedagogically irrelevant musical skills and knowledge, trying to fit into the round holes of a pedagogy with which they have no professional or scholarly connection. Acknowledgements I am indebted to Yaroslav Senyshyn for his comments on this paper and also to doctoral student, Akosua Addo, for her invaluable help in supplying me with the Ghanaian terms and definitions. References Anderson, E. (ed. and trans) (1938). The letters of Mozart and his family (revised edn. 1985). London. Baumgarten, A.G. (1750). Aesthetica. (1961 edn). Hildesheim: G. Olms. Cage, J. (1939). Silence. London: Calder and Boyars. Castiglione, B. (1528). Il libro del Cortegiano. Venice . Elliott, D. (1994). Rethinking music: first steps to a new philosophy of music education. International Journal of Music Education , 24, 9-20. Foucault, M. (1966). The order of things: an archaeology of the human sciences. First published in English in 1970. London: Tavistock. Rouget, G. (1985) Music and trance: a theory of relations between music and possession. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Walker, R. (1984). Music education: tradition and innovation Springfield Ill: Charles C. Thomas. Walker, R. (1990). Musical beliefs: mythic, psychoacoustic, and educational perspectives. Teachers College Press: New York. Wellesz, I. (ed.) (1957). Ancient and Oriental music. Vol 1, The New Oxford History of Music. Oxford: Oxford University Press. L'6ducation musicale liber6e du coloniaiisnxei un nouvel e~~ Cet article argumente contre les sp6cifiques culturels (i.e. de l'ouest) et universels en th6orie retouv6 en musique et en education musicale. L'article accuse la pratique g6n6rale en education musicales d'avoir perdu contact avec les pratiques contemporaines des musiciens, ceci isolant 1'6ducation musicale des autres pratiques 6ducationelles. Décrit comme ayant en tate les objectifs de 1'ISI~E au point de vue de la musique et de 1'education musicale, ces probl6ines sont serieux. L'article indique que l'usage de la terminologie de l'ouest est inimical aux buts de 1'ISME. Les termes cornrne 'la musique' et `1'~sthetique' sont purement de 1'ouest. Des relations epist6mologiques existent entre une th6orie esth6tique et les pratiques musicales associ6es, mats celles-ci ne sont pas universelles. Vom Kolonialismus befreite B4usikerziehungi neue Praxis Der Beitrag wendet sich gegen die Verschmelzung des kulturell Spezifischen (d.h. des Abendlandischen) mit dem Universellen im theoretischen Diskurs iiber Musik und Musikerziehung. Er erhebt den Vorwurf, daB die Praxis der Musikerziehung sich im allgemeinen von der Praxis der gegenwdrtig praktizierenden Musiker entfernt hat und so die 1915 Musikerziehung von anderen erzieherischen Praktiken isoliert hat. Im Zusammenhang von ISMEs Verpflichtung gegeniiber einer weltweiten Betrachtung der Musik sind solche Probleme ernstzunehmen. Der Beitrag argumentiert, daB der Gebrauch der westerlichen Terminologie den Zielen von ISME vviderspriclat, Eegrif~e wie 'Musik' und `Asthetik' sind spezifisch westlich. Epistemologische Verbindungen existieren zwischen einer 5sthetiscben Theorie und der damit verbundenen musikalischen Praxis, aber diese sind nicht allgemeingiiltig. La educaci6n musical liberada del coloniaiisnxoi una nueva practica Este trabajo argumenta en contra de la fusi6n de lo especificauiente cultural (es decir, occidente) y lo universal, en el discurso teorico sobre la musica y la educaci6n musical. Se recrimina que la practica de la educaci6n musical en general ha perdido contacto con las prdcticas contemporáneas de los musics, aislando en consecuencia a la educaci6n musical de otras prdcticas educativas. Dentro del contexto del compromise de la ISME hacia una perspectiva mundial de la musica y de la educaci6n musical, tales problemas son serios. Se argumenta que el uso de la terminologia occidental es adverso a los objetivos de la ISME. Términos tales como musica y est6tica son especificamente occidentales. Existen lazos epistemol6gicos entre una teoria est6tica y las prdcticas musicales asociadas, pero 6stas no son universales.</full_text>
</body>
<references>
<citation>
<book-ref>
<edg>
<editor>Anderson, E.</editor>
</edg>
(ed. and trans) (
<dte>1938</dte>
).
<btl>The letters of Mozart and his family</btl>
(revised edn.
<dte>1985</dte>
).
<pub-ref>
<pub-place>London</pub-place>
</pub-ref>
.</book-ref>
</citation>
<citation>
<book-ref>
<aut>
<au>Baumgarten, A.G.</au>
</aut>
(
<dte>1750</dte>
).
<btl>Aesthetica</btl>
. (
<dte>1961</dte>
edn).
<pub-ref>
<pub-place>Hildesheim</pub-place>
:
<pub-name>G. Olms.</pub-name>
</pub-ref>
</book-ref>
</citation>
<citation>
<book-ref>
<aut>
<au>Cage, J.</au>
</aut>
(
<dte>1939</dte>
).
<btl>Silence</btl>
.
<pub-ref>
<pub-place>London</pub-place>
:
<pub-name>Calder and Boyars</pub-name>
</pub-ref>
.</book-ref>
</citation>
<citation>
<book-ref>
<aut>
<au>Castiglione, B.</au>
</aut>
(
<dte>1528</dte>
).
<btl>Il libro del Cortegiano</btl>
.
<pub-ref>
<pub-place>Venice</pub-place>
</pub-ref>
.</book-ref>
</citation>
<citation>
<journal-ref>
<aut>
<au>Elliott, D.</au>
</aut>
(
<dte>1994</dte>
).
<art-ref>
<atl>Rethinking music: first steps to a new philosophy of music education. International Journal of Music</atl>
</art-ref>
<jtl>Education</jtl>
,
<vid>24</vid>
,
<art-ref>
<ppf>9</ppf>
-
<ppl>20</ppl>
</art-ref>
.</journal-ref>
</citation>
<citation>
<book-ref>
<aut>
<au>Foucault, M.</au>
</aut>
(
<dte>1966</dte>
).
<btl>The order of things: an archaeology of the human sciences</btl>
. First published in English in
<dte>1970</dte>
.
<pub-ref>
<pub-place>London</pub-place>
:
<pub-name>Tavistock</pub-name>
</pub-ref>
.</book-ref>
</citation>
<citation>
<book-ref>
<aut>
<au>Rouget, G.</au>
</aut>
(
<dte>1985</dte>
)
<btl>Music and trance: a theory of relations between music and possession</btl>
.
<pub-ref>
<pub-place>Chicago</pub-place>
:
<pub-name>University of Chicago Press</pub-name>
</pub-ref>
.</book-ref>
</citation>
<citation>
<book-ref>
<aut>
<au>Walker, R.</au>
</aut>
(
<dte>1984</dte>
).
<btl>Music education: tradition and innovation</btl>
<pub-ref>
<pub-place>Springfield Ill</pub-place>
:
<pub-name>Charles C. Thomas.</pub-name>
</pub-ref>
</book-ref>
</citation>
<citation>
<book-ref>
<aut>
<au>Walker, R.</au>
</aut>
(
<dte>1990</dte>
).
<btl>Musical beliefs: mythic, psychoacoustic, and educational perspectives</btl>
.
<pub-ref>
<pub-name>Teachers College Press</pub-name>
:
<pub-place>New York</pub-place>
</pub-ref>
.</book-ref>
</citation>
<citation>
<book-ref>
<edg>
<editor>Wellesz, I.</editor>
</edg>
(ed.) (
<dte>1957</dte>
).
<btl>Ancient and Oriental music. Vol 1, The</btl>
<pub-ref>
<pub-place>New</pub-place>
</pub-ref>
<pub-ref>
<pub-place>Oxford</pub-place>
</pub-ref>
History of Music.
<pub-ref>
<pub-place>Oxford</pub-place>
:
<pub-name>Oxford University Press</pub-name>
</pub-ref>
.</book-ref>
</citation>
</references>
</SAGEmeta>
</istex:document>
</istex:metadataXml>
<mods version="3.6">
<titleInfo>
<title>Music education freed from colonialism: a new praxis</title>
</titleInfo>
<titleInfo type="alternative">
<title>Music education freed from colonialism: a new praxis</title>
</titleInfo>
<name type="personal">
<namePart type="given">Robert</namePart>
<namePart type="family">Walker</namePart>
<affiliation>University of British Columbia, Vancouver, Canada</affiliation>
<role>
<roleTerm type="text">author</roleTerm>
</role>
</name>
<typeOfResource>text</typeOfResource>
<genre type="research-article" displayLabel="Journal Article" authority="ISTEX" authorityURI="https://content-type.data.istex.fr" valueURI="https://content-type.data.istex.fr/ark:/67375/XTP-1JC4F85T-7">research-article</genre>
<originInfo>
<publisher>Sage Publications</publisher>
<place>
<placeTerm type="text">Sage CA: Thousand Oaks, CA</placeTerm>
</place>
<dateIssued encoding="w3cdtf">1996</dateIssued>
<copyrightDate encoding="w3cdtf">1996</copyrightDate>
</originInfo>
<abstract>This paper argues against a conflation of the culturally specific (i.e. the western) and the universal in theoretical discourse about music and music education. The charge is made that music education practices generally have lost touch with the contemporary practices of musicians, thus isolating music education from other educational practices. Set in a context of ISME's commitment to a world view of music and music education, such problems are serious. It is argued that the use of western terminology is inimical to ISME's goals. Terms like 'music' and 'aesthetic' are specifically western. Epistemological links exist between an aesthetic theory and the associated musical practices, but these are not universal.</abstract>
<relatedItem type="host">
<titleInfo>
<title>International Journal of Music Education</title>
</titleInfo>
<genre type="journal" authority="ISTEX" authorityURI="https://publication-type.data.istex.fr" valueURI="https://publication-type.data.istex.fr/ark:/67375/JMC-0GLKJH51-B">journal</genre>
<originInfo>
<publisher>Sage</publisher>
</originInfo>
<part>
<date>1996</date>
<detail type="volume">
<caption>vol.</caption>
<number>27</number>
</detail>
<detail type="issue">
<caption>no.</caption>
<number>1</number>
</detail>
<extent unit="pages">
<start>2</start>
<end>15</end>
</extent>
</part>
<identifier type="ISSN">0255-7614</identifier>
</relatedItem>
<identifier type="istex">21ED2F57E141C4FAC8AACDD069E6B548457AA513</identifier>
<identifier type="ark">ark:/67375/M70-NSW663Q1-0</identifier>
<identifier type="DOI">10.1177/025576149602700102</identifier>
<recordInfo>
<recordContentSource authority="ISTEX" authorityURI="https://loaded-corpus.data.istex.fr" valueURI="https://loaded-corpus.data.istex.fr/ark:/67375/XBH-0J1N7DQT-B">sage</recordContentSource>
<recordOrigin>Sage Publications</recordOrigin>
</recordInfo>
</mods>
<json:item>
<extension>json</extension>
<original>false</original>
<mimetype>application/json</mimetype>
<uri>https://api.istex.fr/document/21ED2F57E141C4FAC8AACDD069E6B548457AA513/metadata/json</uri>
</json:item>
</metadata>
<serie></serie>
</istex>
</record>

Pour manipuler ce document sous Unix (Dilib)

EXPLOR_STEP=$WICRI_ROOT/Wicri/Musique/explor/DebussyV1/Data/Istex/Corpus
HfdSelect -h $EXPLOR_STEP/biblio.hfd -nk 002167 | SxmlIndent | more

Ou

HfdSelect -h $EXPLOR_AREA/Data/Istex/Corpus/biblio.hfd -nk 002167 | SxmlIndent | more

Pour mettre un lien sur cette page dans le réseau Wicri

{{Explor lien
   |wiki=    Wicri/Musique
   |area=    DebussyV1
   |flux=    Istex
   |étape=   Corpus
   |type=    RBID
   |clé=     ISTEX:21ED2F57E141C4FAC8AACDD069E6B548457AA513
   |texte=   Music education freed from colonialism: a new praxis
}}

Wicri

This area was generated with Dilib version V0.6.33.
Data generation: Tue Sep 25 16:34:07 2018. Site generation: Mon Mar 11 10:31:28 2024