Serveur d'exploration sur les dispositifs haptiques

Attention, ce site est en cours de développement !
Attention, site généré par des moyens informatiques à partir de corpus bruts.
Les informations ne sont donc pas validées.

Control your mind, make affordance available

Identifieur interne : 000671 ( Pmc/Checkpoint ); précédent : 000670; suivant : 000672

Control your mind, make affordance available

Auteurs : Zheng Jin [République populaire de Chine, États-Unis] ; Yang Lee [Corée du Sud, États-Unis] ; Jin Zhu [République populaire de Chine]

Source :

RBID : PMC:4330679

Abstract

Evaluating the affordance–control interpretation of the relationship between performance and object estimation has been proposed by psychophysical and psychonomic studies. This study examined the weight estimation–performance relationship. Individuals with visual impairment or blindness put shots that varied in weight among five scales. In Experiment 1, only the perceived weight was a significant performance constraint. In Experiment 2, the weight was perceived as heavier when the participants’ actions were manipulated through cognitive interpretation. The increase in perceived weight appeared to be related to performance and intrinsically scaled to the action, even when the action was only mental rather than physical. The study’s findings suggest that bodily experience and action are the basis for physical judgments and likely underlie other basic cognitive interpretations of sensory stimuli. This suggestion goes hand in hand with the biofunctional approaches which assume direct experience of the integrated wholeness of one’s body is fundamental for developing other kinds of awareness. Different perspectives from oriental philosophy and psychology are also discussed.


Url:
DOI: 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00096
PubMed: 25741298
PubMed Central: 4330679


Affiliations:


Links toward previous steps (curation, corpus...)


Links to Exploration step

PMC:4330679

Le document en format XML

<record>
<TEI>
<teiHeader>
<fileDesc>
<titleStmt>
<title xml:lang="en">Control your mind, make affordance available</title>
<author>
<name sortKey="Jin, Zheng" sort="Jin, Zheng" uniqKey="Jin Z" first="Zheng" last="Jin">Zheng Jin</name>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff1">
<institution>Institute of Educational Science, Zhengzhou Normal University</institution>
,
<country>Zhengzhou, China</country>
</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">République populaire de Chine</country>
<wicri:regionArea></wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:regionArea># see nlm:aff region in country</wicri:regionArea>
</affiliation>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff2">
<institution>Department of Psychology, University of California</institution>
,
<country>Davis, CA, USA</country>
</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">États-Unis</country>
<wicri:regionArea></wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:regionArea># see nlm:aff region in country</wicri:regionArea>
</affiliation>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Lee, Yang" sort="Lee, Yang" uniqKey="Lee Y" first="Yang" last="Lee">Yang Lee</name>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff3">
<institution>Department of Psychology, Gyeongsang National University</institution>
,
<country>Jinju, South Korea</country>
</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">Corée du Sud</country>
<wicri:regionArea></wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:regionArea># see nlm:aff region in country</wicri:regionArea>
</affiliation>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff4">
<institution>Haskins Laboratories, Yale University</institution>
,
<country>New Heaven, CT, USA</country>
</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">États-Unis</country>
<wicri:regionArea></wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:regionArea># see nlm:aff region in country</wicri:regionArea>
</affiliation>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Zhu, Jin" sort="Zhu, Jin" uniqKey="Zhu J" first="Jin" last="Zhu">Jin Zhu</name>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff5">
<institution>Yunnan University of Nationalities</institution>
,
<country>Kunming, China</country>
</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">République populaire de Chine</country>
<wicri:regionArea></wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:regionArea># see nlm:aff region in country</wicri:regionArea>
</affiliation>
</author>
</titleStmt>
<publicationStmt>
<idno type="wicri:source">PMC</idno>
<idno type="pmid">25741298</idno>
<idno type="pmc">4330679</idno>
<idno type="url">http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC4330679</idno>
<idno type="RBID">PMC:4330679</idno>
<idno type="doi">10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00096</idno>
<date when="2015">2015</date>
<idno type="wicri:Area/Pmc/Corpus">001F32</idno>
<idno type="wicri:Area/Pmc/Curation">001F32</idno>
<idno type="wicri:Area/Pmc/Checkpoint">000671</idno>
</publicationStmt>
<sourceDesc>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<title xml:lang="en" level="a" type="main">Control your mind, make affordance available</title>
<author>
<name sortKey="Jin, Zheng" sort="Jin, Zheng" uniqKey="Jin Z" first="Zheng" last="Jin">Zheng Jin</name>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff1">
<institution>Institute of Educational Science, Zhengzhou Normal University</institution>
,
<country>Zhengzhou, China</country>
</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">République populaire de Chine</country>
<wicri:regionArea></wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:regionArea># see nlm:aff region in country</wicri:regionArea>
</affiliation>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff2">
<institution>Department of Psychology, University of California</institution>
,
<country>Davis, CA, USA</country>
</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">États-Unis</country>
<wicri:regionArea></wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:regionArea># see nlm:aff region in country</wicri:regionArea>
</affiliation>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Lee, Yang" sort="Lee, Yang" uniqKey="Lee Y" first="Yang" last="Lee">Yang Lee</name>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff3">
<institution>Department of Psychology, Gyeongsang National University</institution>
,
<country>Jinju, South Korea</country>
</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">Corée du Sud</country>
<wicri:regionArea></wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:regionArea># see nlm:aff region in country</wicri:regionArea>
</affiliation>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff4">
<institution>Haskins Laboratories, Yale University</institution>
,
<country>New Heaven, CT, USA</country>
</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">États-Unis</country>
<wicri:regionArea></wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:regionArea># see nlm:aff region in country</wicri:regionArea>
</affiliation>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Zhu, Jin" sort="Zhu, Jin" uniqKey="Zhu J" first="Jin" last="Zhu">Jin Zhu</name>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff5">
<institution>Yunnan University of Nationalities</institution>
,
<country>Kunming, China</country>
</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">République populaire de Chine</country>
<wicri:regionArea></wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:regionArea># see nlm:aff region in country</wicri:regionArea>
</affiliation>
</author>
</analytic>
<series>
<title level="j">Frontiers in Psychology</title>
<idno type="eISSN">1664-1078</idno>
<imprint>
<date when="2015">2015</date>
</imprint>
</series>
</biblStruct>
</sourceDesc>
</fileDesc>
<profileDesc>
<textClass></textClass>
</profileDesc>
</teiHeader>
<front>
<div type="abstract" xml:lang="en">
<p>Evaluating the affordance–control interpretation of the relationship between performance and object estimation has been proposed by psychophysical and psychonomic studies. This study examined the weight estimation–performance relationship. Individuals with visual impairment or blindness put shots that varied in weight among five scales. In Experiment 1, only the perceived weight was a significant performance constraint. In Experiment 2, the weight was perceived as heavier when the participants’ actions were manipulated through cognitive interpretation. The increase in perceived weight appeared to be related to performance and intrinsically scaled to the action, even when the action was only mental rather than physical. The study’s findings suggest that bodily experience and action are the basis for physical judgments and likely underlie other basic cognitive interpretations of sensory stimuli. This suggestion goes hand in hand with the biofunctional approaches which assume direct experience of the integrated wholeness of one’s body is fundamental for developing other kinds of awareness. Different perspectives from oriental philosophy and psychology are also discussed.</p>
</div>
</front>
<back>
<div1 type="bibliography">
<listBibl>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Ashby, F G" uniqKey="Ashby F">F. G. Ashby</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Townsend, J T" uniqKey="Townsend J">J. T. Townsend</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Bargh, J A" uniqKey="Bargh J">J. A. Bargh</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Chen, M" uniqKey="Chen M">M. Chen</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Burrows, L" uniqKey="Burrows L">L. Burrows</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Bays, P M" uniqKey="Bays P">P. M. Bays</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Flanagan, J R" uniqKey="Flanagan J">J. R. Flanagan</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Wolpert, D M" uniqKey="Wolpert D">D. M. Wolpert</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Bhalla, M" uniqKey="Bhalla M">M. Bhalla</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Proffitt, D R" uniqKey="Proffitt D">D. R. Proffitt</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Brown, K W" uniqKey="Brown K">K. W. Brown</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Cordon, S" uniqKey="Cordon S">S. Cordon</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Caiani, S Z" uniqKey="Caiani S">S. Z. Caiani</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Ca Al Bruland, R" uniqKey="Ca Al Bruland R">R. Cañal-Bruland</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Van Der Kamp, J" uniqKey="Van Der Kamp J">J. van der Kamp</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Carlson, V R" uniqKey="Carlson V">V. R. Carlson</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Doyen, S" uniqKey="Doyen S">S. Doyen</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Klein, O" uniqKey="Klein O">O. Klein</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Pichon, C L" uniqKey="Pichon C">C. L. Pichon</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Cleeremans, A" uniqKey="Cleeremans A">A. Cleeremans</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Ellis, B" uniqKey="Ellis B">B. Ellis</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Fajen, B R" uniqKey="Fajen B">B. R. Fajen</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Fajen, B R" uniqKey="Fajen B">B. R. Fajen</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Phillips, F" uniqKey="Phillips F">F. Phillips</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Fajen, B R" uniqKey="Fajen B">B. R. Fajen</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Riley, M R" uniqKey="Riley M">M. R. Riley</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Turvey, M T" uniqKey="Turvey M">M. T. Turvey</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Gibson, J J" uniqKey="Gibson J">J. J. Gibson</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Grezes, J" uniqKey="Grezes J">J. Grezes</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Decety, J" uniqKey="Decety J">J. Decety</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Harber, K" uniqKey="Harber K">K. Harber</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Yeung, D" uniqKey="Yeung D">D. Yeung</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Iacovelli, A" uniqKey="Iacovelli A">A. Iacovelli</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Iran Nejad, A" uniqKey="Iran Nejad A">A. Iran-Nejad</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Jin, Z" uniqKey="Jin Z">Z. Jin</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Lee, Y" uniqKey="Lee Y">Y. Lee</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Lee, E H" uniqKey="Lee E">E. H. Lee</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Schnall, S" uniqKey="Schnall S">S. Schnall</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Lee, Y" uniqKey="Lee Y">Y. Lee</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Lee, S" uniqKey="Lee S">S. Lee</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Carello, C" uniqKey="Carello C">C. Carello</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Turvey, M T" uniqKey="Turvey M">M. T. Turvey</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Lee, Y" uniqKey="Lee Y">Y. Lee</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Park, H" uniqKey="Park H">H. Park</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Ko, J" uniqKey="Ko J">J. Ko</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Shin, K" uniqKey="Shin K">K. Shin</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Lee, N" uniqKey="Lee N">N. Lee</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Shaw, R" uniqKey="Shaw R">R. Shaw</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Miller, G" uniqKey="Miller G">G. Miller</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Millikan, R G" uniqKey="Millikan R">R. G. Millikan</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Oberle, C D" uniqKey="Oberle C">C. D. Oberle</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Amazeen, E L" uniqKey="Amazeen E">E. L. Amazeen</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Proffitt, D R" uniqKey="Proffitt D">D. R. Proffitt</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Linkenauger, S A" uniqKey="Linkenauger S">S. A. Linkenauger</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Proffitt, D R" uniqKey="Proffitt D">D. R. Proffitt</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Stefanucci, J K" uniqKey="Stefanucci J">J. K. Stefanucci</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Banton, T" uniqKey="Banton T">T. Banton</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Epstein, W" uniqKey="Epstein W">W. Epstein</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Robinson, P" uniqKey="Robinson P">P. Robinson</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Rosch, E" uniqKey="Rosch E">E. Rosch</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Rosch, E" uniqKey="Rosch E">E. Rosch</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Shapiro, L A" uniqKey="Shapiro L">L. A. Shapiro</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Shockley, K" uniqKey="Shockley K">K. Shockley</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Carello, C" uniqKey="Carello C">C. Carello</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Turvey, M T" uniqKey="Turvey M">M. T. Turvey</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Turvey, M T" uniqKey="Turvey M">M. T. Turvey</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Turvey, M T" uniqKey="Turvey M">M. T. Turvey</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Carello, C" uniqKey="Carello C">C. Carello</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Ullman, S" uniqKey="Ullman S">S. Ullman</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Witt, J K" uniqKey="Witt J">J. K. Witt</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Witt, J K" uniqKey="Witt J">J. K. Witt</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Dorsch, T" uniqKey="Dorsch T">T. Dorsch</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Witt, J K" uniqKey="Witt J">J. K. Witt</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Linkenauger, S A" uniqKey="Linkenauger S">S. A. Linkenauger</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Bakdash, J Z" uniqKey="Bakdash J">J. Z. Bakdash</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Proffitt, D R" uniqKey="Proffitt D">D. R. Proffitt</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Witt, J K" uniqKey="Witt J">J. K. Witt</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Proffitt, D R" uniqKey="Proffitt D">D. R. Proffitt</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Witt, J K" uniqKey="Witt J">J. K. Witt</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Proffitt, D R" uniqKey="Proffitt D">D. R. Proffitt</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Epstein, W" uniqKey="Epstein W">W. Epstein</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Witt, J K" uniqKey="Witt J">J. K. Witt</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Sugovic, M" uniqKey="Sugovic M">M. Sugovic</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Yong, E" uniqKey="Yong E">E. Yong</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
</listBibl>
</div1>
</back>
</TEI>
<pmc article-type="research-article">
<pmc-dir>properties open_access</pmc-dir>
<front>
<journal-meta>
<journal-id journal-id-type="nlm-ta">Front Psychol</journal-id>
<journal-id journal-id-type="iso-abbrev">Front Psychol</journal-id>
<journal-id journal-id-type="publisher-id">Front. Psychol.</journal-id>
<journal-title-group>
<journal-title>Frontiers in Psychology</journal-title>
</journal-title-group>
<issn pub-type="epub">1664-1078</issn>
<publisher>
<publisher-name>Frontiers Media S.A.</publisher-name>
</publisher>
</journal-meta>
<article-meta>
<article-id pub-id-type="pmid">25741298</article-id>
<article-id pub-id-type="pmc">4330679</article-id>
<article-id pub-id-type="doi">10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00096</article-id>
<article-categories>
<subj-group subj-group-type="heading">
<subject>Psychology</subject>
<subj-group>
<subject>Hypothesis & Theory Article</subject>
</subj-group>
</subj-group>
</article-categories>
<title-group>
<article-title>Control your mind, make affordance available</article-title>
</title-group>
<contrib-group>
<contrib contrib-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Jin</surname>
<given-names>Zheng</given-names>
</name>
<xref ref-type="aff" rid="aff1">
<sup>1</sup>
</xref>
<xref ref-type="aff" rid="aff2">
<sup>2</sup>
</xref>
<xref ref-type="author-notes" rid="fn001">
<sup>*</sup>
</xref>
<uri xlink:type="simple" xlink:href="http://community.frontiersin.org/people/u/177392"></uri>
</contrib>
<contrib contrib-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Lee</surname>
<given-names>Yang</given-names>
</name>
<xref ref-type="aff" rid="aff3">
<sup>3</sup>
</xref>
<xref ref-type="aff" rid="aff4">
<sup>4</sup>
</xref>
</contrib>
<contrib contrib-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Zhu</surname>
<given-names>Jin</given-names>
</name>
<xref ref-type="aff" rid="aff5">
<sup>5</sup>
</xref>
</contrib>
</contrib-group>
<aff id="aff1">
<sup>1</sup>
<institution>Institute of Educational Science, Zhengzhou Normal University</institution>
,
<country>Zhengzhou, China</country>
</aff>
<aff id="aff2">
<sup>2</sup>
<institution>Department of Psychology, University of California</institution>
,
<country>Davis, CA, USA</country>
</aff>
<aff id="aff3">
<sup>3</sup>
<institution>Department of Psychology, Gyeongsang National University</institution>
,
<country>Jinju, South Korea</country>
</aff>
<aff id="aff4">
<sup>4</sup>
<institution>Haskins Laboratories, Yale University</institution>
,
<country>New Heaven, CT, USA</country>
</aff>
<aff id="aff5">
<sup>5</sup>
<institution>Yunnan University of Nationalities</institution>
,
<country>Kunming, China</country>
</aff>
<author-notes>
<fn fn-type="edited-by">
<p>Edited by:
<italic>Franco Zengaro, Delta State University, USA</italic>
</p>
</fn>
<fn fn-type="edited-by">
<p>Reviewed by:
<italic>Costantini Marcello, University of Chieti, Italy; André Klostermann, University of Bern, Switzerland</italic>
</p>
</fn>
<corresp id="fn001">*Correspondence:
<italic>Zheng Jin, Institute of Educational Science, Zhengzhou Normal University, 1-316, 6, Yingcai Street, 450044 Zhengzhou, China e-mail:
<email xlink:type="simple">zhjin@ucdavis.edu</email>
</italic>
</corresp>
<fn fn-type="other" id="fn002">
<p>This article was submitted to Cognition, a section of the journal Frontiers in Psychology.</p>
</fn>
</author-notes>
<pub-date pub-type="epub">
<day>17</day>
<month>2</month>
<year>2015</year>
</pub-date>
<pub-date pub-type="collection">
<year>2015</year>
</pub-date>
<volume>6</volume>
<elocation-id>96</elocation-id>
<history>
<date date-type="received">
<day>14</day>
<month>9</month>
<year>2014</year>
</date>
<date date-type="accepted">
<day>18</day>
<month>1</month>
<year>2015</year>
</date>
</history>
<permissions>
<copyright-statement>Copyright © 2015 Jin, Lee and Zhu.</copyright-statement>
<copyright-year>2015</copyright-year>
<license license-type="open-access" xlink:href="http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/">
<license-p>This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.</license-p>
</license>
</permissions>
<abstract>
<p>Evaluating the affordance–control interpretation of the relationship between performance and object estimation has been proposed by psychophysical and psychonomic studies. This study examined the weight estimation–performance relationship. Individuals with visual impairment or blindness put shots that varied in weight among five scales. In Experiment 1, only the perceived weight was a significant performance constraint. In Experiment 2, the weight was perceived as heavier when the participants’ actions were manipulated through cognitive interpretation. The increase in perceived weight appeared to be related to performance and intrinsically scaled to the action, even when the action was only mental rather than physical. The study’s findings suggest that bodily experience and action are the basis for physical judgments and likely underlie other basic cognitive interpretations of sensory stimuli. This suggestion goes hand in hand with the biofunctional approaches which assume direct experience of the integrated wholeness of one’s body is fundamental for developing other kinds of awareness. Different perspectives from oriental philosophy and psychology are also discussed.</p>
</abstract>
<kwd-group>
<kwd>affordance control</kwd>
<kwd>ecological approach</kwd>
<kwd>action</kwd>
<kwd>perception</kwd>
<kwd>biofunctional understanding</kwd>
<kwd>embodied cognition</kwd>
</kwd-group>
<counts>
<fig-count count="3"></fig-count>
<table-count count="1"></table-count>
<equation-count count="0"></equation-count>
<ref-count count="41"></ref-count>
<page-count count="6"></page-count>
<word-count count="5350"></word-count>
</counts>
</article-meta>
</front>
<body>
<sec sec-type="intro">
<title>INTRODUCTION</title>
<p>Action-specific perception theory (or perception–action relation) proposes that people perceive the environment in terms of their ability to act in it (
<xref rid="B14" ref-type="bibr">Gibson, 1979</xref>
;
<xref rid="B35" ref-type="bibr">Witt, 2011</xref>
). It has guided biofunctional studies on the relationship of perception to motor control (e.g.,
<xref rid="B15" ref-type="bibr">Grezes and Decety, 2001</xref>
). On the assumption that judgments and productions of target size are good proxies for perceived target size, studies (e.g.,
<xref rid="B39" ref-type="bibr">Witt et al., 2010</xref>
) have interpreted the empirically observed performance-estimated size relationship as a performance–perception relationship. In goal-directed tasks, when a player’s performance is better, the player’s estimate of the target size is larger (e.g.,
<xref rid="B38" ref-type="bibr">Witt and Proffitt, 2005</xref>
;
<xref rid="B37" ref-type="bibr">Witt et al., 2008</xref>
;
<xref rid="B7" ref-type="bibr">Cañal-Bruland and van der Kamp, 2009</xref>
;
<xref rid="B36" ref-type="bibr">Witt and Dorsch, 2009</xref>
), and the mean estimate is larger for players with more easily performed tasks (e.g.,
<xref rid="B4" ref-type="bibr">Bhalla and Proffitt, 1999</xref>
;
<xref rid="B26" ref-type="bibr">Proffitt et al., 2003</xref>
). Accordingly, this thesis has advanced that optical variables, such as those that pertain to hitting a softball or putting a golf ball, are scaled by metrics that emerge from action-specific body organization (e.g.,
<xref rid="B25" ref-type="bibr">Proffitt and Linkenauger, 2013</xref>
). Following this argument, a person who performs well perceives targets (e.g., balls, holes) to be larger.</p>
<p>In general, these kinds of experiments share a number of features. First, participants have explicit knowledge of their performance levels prior to their making any size judgments (e.g.,
<xref rid="B38" ref-type="bibr">Witt and Proffitt, 2005</xref>
;
<xref rid="B37" ref-type="bibr">Witt et al., 2008</xref>
). Second, the target is of a single size (e.g., a softball or golf cup). Third, participants make size judgments subsequent to extending the full trial complement. Thus, the cognitive reevaluation of the goal size in light of the estimated accuracy, in a sense, is not ruled out, and thus, the link between perceived size and hit rate (i.e., performance) may not be causal. Additionally, it is unknown whether the participants were equally and implicitly aware of both the actual and the retinal sizes of the targets. That is, the dependence of miniature selection on the proximal–distal fit could not be measured. In addition, performance would be expected to improve systematically with target size. In addition to any variations in actual target size, whether there was a performance-estimated size relationship could not be measured. For the above reasons, studies fail to provide a full understanding of the performance-estimated size relationship.</p>
<p>A novel method was thus introduced to provide less-explicit visual knowledge of participants’ performance results (
<xref rid="B20" ref-type="bibr">Lee et al., 2012</xref>
). Participants were confronted with multiple target sizes rather than one, and they estimated target size during each trial rather than after each round. It was found that target size judgments correlate with prior success in hitting the target. In affordances, the manner in which one uses his or her body to interact with the environment affects his or her perception of the environment. A later study supplemented findings by
<xref rid="B18" ref-type="bibr">Jin and Lee (2013)</xref>
and reinforced the notion of affordance-based control. On these grounds, the action-specific approach not only provides robust evidence for the account of affordances but also suggests that perception is mediated by internal processes by demonstrating a new ontology for the behavioral sciences based on biologically relevant affordances rather than physical objects (
<xref rid="B18" ref-type="bibr">Jin and Lee, 2013</xref>
; also see
<xref rid="B32" ref-type="bibr">Turvey, 1992</xref>
;
<xref rid="B22" ref-type="bibr">Miller, 2007</xref>
).</p>
<p>Perception is one’s only information source about the external world and has been explained in many ways (
<xref rid="B40" ref-type="bibr">Witt and Sugovic, 2013</xref>
); larger perceived goal sizes have been associated with performance and are affected by the types of actions. If people are unaware of their performance, then what coordinates the relationship between perception and performance? Further, how can a person reliably produce a beneficial perceptual change (e.g., amplification) in performance? The embodied cognition holds that the nature of the human mind is largely determined by the form of the human body (
<xref rid="B30" ref-type="bibr">Shapiro, 2011</xref>
). Despite the common biofunctional orientation between action-specific perception and embodied cognition, analytic approach that captures the “intuitions” we have about human functioning has not been well developed in these fields. We are invited to more seriously consider the philosophical issue of the “natural kind or proper observable” (
<xref rid="B23" ref-type="bibr">Millikan, 1999</xref>
;
<xref rid="B10" ref-type="bibr">Ellis, 2001</xref>
, also see
<xref rid="B29" ref-type="bibr">Rosch, 2000</xref>
), for which perception is a proxy in these types of experiments. A different paradigm is proposed here of explaining the relationship between action and object estimation, and this explanation might be independent of the physical action status, in contrast to the purely cognitive processes that render affordance available.</p>
</sec>
<sec>
<title>EXPERIMENT 1</title>
<sec>
<title>PARTICIPANTS</title>
<p>Nine individuals with blindness (one female and eight males), aged 31–42 years (
<italic>M</italic>
= 36.88 year, SD = 2.90), were recruited with the assistance of the provincial Disabled Persons Federation. Of the nine participants, six were adventitiously blind and three were congenitally blind. Total blindness was a universal characteristic, and the age at sight loss ranged from 0 (congenitally blind) to 33 years old. The subjects were orally informed of the consent agreement. One participant (female) was excluded from the analysis because she withdrew during the tasks. The participants were paid 50 Chinese yuan (CNY) as compensation. Because the sample size was similar to the study by Lee and colleagues (
<xref rid="B20" ref-type="bibr">Lee et al., 2012</xref>
;
<xref rid="B18" ref-type="bibr">Jin and Lee, 2013</xref>
) and smaller than the study by Witt and colleagues (
<xref rid="B38" ref-type="bibr">Witt and Proffitt, 2005</xref>
;
<xref rid="B37" ref-type="bibr">Witt et al., 2008</xref>
), for a direct comparison, we report rank-order correlation coefficients (see
<italic>results</italic>
below).</p>
</sec>
<sec>
<title>MATERIALS</title>
<p>The experiment was conducted in a field with ample surroundings. The participants were instructed to put five artificial shots with varying weights as far as they could. The standard weight is 3 kg (3000 g); the weights of the five shots used in this study were 1000, 2000, 3000, 4000, and 5000 g (Figure
<xref ref-type="fig" rid="F1">1</xref>
). The diagonal lines of these shots were identical (13 cm). To provide their weight estimates, the participants selected one of eleven solid balls (diagonal lines, 13 cm), which varied from 500 to 5500 g in 500 g increments.</p>
<fig id="F1" position="float">
<label>FIGURE 1</label>
<caption>
<p>
<bold>A shot and a solid ball used in Experiment 1</bold>
.</p>
</caption>
<graphic xlink:href="fpsyg-06-00096-g0001"></graphic>
</fig>
</sec>
<sec>
<title>PROCEDURE</title>
<p>When the task began, participants were required to hold the shots for approximately 10 s and then use a standard putting method without run-up (Figure
<xref ref-type="fig" rid="F2">2</xref>
), as taught by the experimenters, before proceeding to the experiment. Immediately after putting, the participants were required to use the same hand they had used to put to quickly weigh eleven solid balls in turn and then provide an approximate estimate of the weight of the shot they had just put. The instruction “estimate a weight that feels most like the shot you just put” was given. The perceived weight measurements presumed that the participant was implicitly aware of both the physical (the shots) and proximal (the solid balls) weights at equal levels (
<xref rid="B8" ref-type="bibr">Carlson, 1960</xref>
). The separate reports of the two weights are provided independently (
<xref rid="B1" ref-type="bibr">Ashby and Townsend, 1986</xref>
; for a discussion of decisional separability and signal detection, see
<xref rid="B24" ref-type="bibr">Oberle and Amazeen, 2003</xref>
).</p>
<fig id="F2" position="float">
<label>FIGURE 2</label>
<caption>
<p>
<bold>Putting the shot without run-up</bold>
.</p>
</caption>
<graphic xlink:href="fpsyg-06-00096-g0002"></graphic>
</fig>
<p>There were 25 putting trials for each participant, five trials for each shot. The solid balls were randomly assigned, and they varied from trial to trial. The participants were not provided the actual weights of the shots, and the shots’ weights also varied randomly over the trials. After each trial, the shot was taken away, and a new shot was provided by the experimenters. The putting distance was recorded as the performance level. The participants could choose to pause briefly between trials to avoid fatigue.</p>
<p>We used three experimenters: one assisted and instructed the participants throughout the procedure, one recorded the participants’ weight estimations, and one measured the putting distance near the “target” (beyond).</p>
</sec>
<sec>
<title>RESULT AND DISCUSSION</title>
<p>The separate reports between the weights of solid ball and physical shots can be provided independently. However, the
<italic>R square</italic>
value between the perceived and proximal weights of 1000, 2000, 3000, 4000, and 5000 g were 0.69 for the eight participants,
<italic>t</italic>
(38) = 9.20,
<italic>p</italic>
= 3.34e-11 (
<italic>r</italic>
<sub>s</sub>
= 0.83,
<italic>N</italic>
= 40, 1-tailed
<italic>p</italic>
= 1.13e-11), which reveals that perceived weight depended on the actual shot weight, as well as implying that the participants systematically related their weighing of the solid balls based on the fit between the shot and solid ball weights.</p>
<p>The participants judged the shots as heavier when the actual shots were heavier. The putting distance was also greater when the shots were lighter,
<italic>r</italic>
<sup>2</sup>
= 0.30,
<italic>t</italic>
(38) = –4.05,
<italic>p</italic>
= 2.43e-4 (
<italic>r</italic>
<sub>s</sub>
= –0.54,
<italic>N</italic>
= 40, 1-tailed
<italic>p</italic>
= 1.66e-4). Importantly, the putting distance correlated with perceived shot weight (Figure
<xref ref-type="fig" rid="F3">3</xref>
). However, if the perceived weight is considered to be an independent variable rather than dependent variable, multiple regression analysis revealed that only the perceived weight predicted the performance,
<italic>r</italic>
<sup>2</sup>
= 0.53, β = –0.02,
<italic>p</italic>
= 1.24e-7, and the actual shot weight was not a significant constraint for the putting distance,
<italic>p</italic>
= 0.404.</p>
<fig id="F3" position="float">
<label>FIGURE 3</label>
<caption>
<p>
<bold>Mean putting distance for the eight participants against perceived weight (i.e., implicit judgments of proximal weight, but c.f.
<xref rid="B20" ref-type="bibr">Lee et al., 2012</xref>
)</bold>
.</p>
</caption>
<graphic xlink:href="fpsyg-06-00096-g0003"></graphic>
</fig>
<p>The performance–perception relationship could be interpreted using the empirically observed performance–estimation relationship. Many studies have scaled performance using metrics from action-specific body organization (e.g.,
<xref rid="B39" ref-type="bibr">Witt et al., 2010</xref>
). Previous studies also confirm that unitary coordination, which comprises bodily status and action processes (e.g., muscle work), is responsible for the performance–estimation relationship. This coordination determines the performance accuracy (level) relative to the target. The results are in agreement with those provided by
<xref rid="B20" ref-type="bibr">Lee et al. (2012)</xref>
. For example, a person standing by a creek may consider it too wide to jump across, but a person who is running and approaching the creek may have a high chance of a successful jump because the creek is visually narrower when a person is running than when he is standing, which “affords” jumping. As perception improves, the person begins to clearly feel how the body is connected and how actions are naturally integrated systems rather than merely coordinated and controlled separate parts. In this study, putting form is primarily registered by the haptical system (
<xref rid="B33" ref-type="bibr">Turvey and Carello, 2011</xref>
). This suggests that perception was scaled based on the perceived levels of coordination and control for any given action.</p>
<p>Our mental busyness, however, is a distinct distraction from accurate perception and awareness. In fact, it appears as though all of our senses are dulled by thinking (
<xref rid="B5" ref-type="bibr">Brown and Cordon, 2009</xref>
). Therefore, it might be that participants’ cognitive form during putting constrains their immediately subsequent proximal weight judgments. Accordingly, a manipulation that mentally affects the haptically perceptible form, rather than the form
<italic>per se</italic>
, should also affect perceived weight. The second experiment aimed to examine this hypothesis.</p>
</sec>
</sec>
<sec>
<title>EXPERIMENT 2</title>
<sec>
<title>PARTICIPANTS AND MATERIALS</title>
<p>Ten blind men (one female, nine males;
<italic>M</italic>
age = 38.30 year, SD = 3.4) from the same population participated in Experiment 2. Seven were adventitiously blind, and three were congenitally blind. Total blindness was a universal characteristic, with age at loss of sight ranging from 0 (congenitally blind) to 31 years. The same
<italic>apparatus</italic>
from Experiment 1 was used.</p>
</sec>
<sec>
<title>PROCEDURE</title>
<p>Participants were told that if they found the task to be too emotionally taxing or uncomfortable, they could terminate it at any time. The same experimental procedure from Experiment 1 was used with one exception: Experiment 2 included an additional condition, action
<italic>imagination</italic>
. The participants were not informed that they would perform the task in two ways. One task comprised half of the trials; Experiment 2 replicated the detailed procedure from Experiment 1.</p>
<p>The other task constituted the remainder of the trials. The participants were ostensibly asked to take a hearing test, and they were invited to wear a pair of special (Bluetooth) earplugs and listen to an audio document. The participants also received instruction through the earplugs. Prior to the task, the participants were told to imagine that they were walking a long distance for exercise; simultaneously, an audio recording was played with the continuous sound of a blind-guiding stick rhythmically tapping on a road surface, the sound of breathing, a tread sound, and an indication voice stating “you have walked X meters” that was repeated at 18-s intervals using an audio-play device with a remote wireless control. At one minute and a half (00:01:30), an indication voice with the message “you are going to walk uphill on a slope” was presented. As the recording advanced, the stick-tapping rhythm became slower, more gasping accompanied a slower tread sound, and the “X” communicated by the indication voice became shorter. When the rhythm, gasp, and tread frequency reached a certain level, the audio recording did not vary (00:02:30) but played continuously. The participants were then instructed to proceed through the task. The audio recording was constantly played until the task ended. The indication voice stating “you have walked X meters on the slope” and “you are going to finish the exercise in about X minutes” kept repeating, replacing the previous voice, at a certain interval. All of the indication voice messages were triggered by an experimenter. All of the “X” and “certain intervals” in the indication voice were controlled by the experimenter depending on specific conditions. In all of the
<italic>imagination</italic>
trials, the volume was adjusted to suit the participants. For half of the participants, the task involved an
<italic>imagination</italic>
preceded by the other task. In this experiment, each of the five shots (1, 2, 3, 4, and 5 kg) for one task consisted of only two trials. The relevant correlation results involving performance (i.e., putting distance) are discussed in Experiment 1; we did not measure performance in Experiment 2.</p>
<p>Participants received a simple questionnaire that asked about the effectiveness of the imagination task. We asked whether their imagination had involved more events than exercise and whether it had involved more actions than walking. No participant reported more events that were not related to exercise, and three participants reported more actions, i.e., trotting and running. After each task was completed, we also assessed the participants’ moods—“How do you feel right now?”— on a scale of 1 (very good) to 9 (very bad).</p>
</sec>
<sec>
<title>RESULT AND DISCUSSION</title>
<p>There were no effects on the mood test, for
<italic>imagination</italic>
task (
<italic>M</italic>
= 3.70, SD = 1.64), and for
<italic>normal</italic>
task (
<italic>M</italic>
= 4.30, SD = 0.95). The main effects of
<italic>imagination</italic>
(two tasks), task order and actual shot weight (five weights) as well as the interaction effects were tested using the analysis of variance (ANOVA). The mean perceived weights were 2990.2 g (SD = 1250.65) for the normal task and 3220.60 g (SD = 1300.97) for the
<italic>imagination</italic>
task. The difference was significant,
<italic>F</italic>
(1,8) = 30.76,
<italic>p</italic>
= 0.001, η
<sup>2</sup>
= 0.79. A strong significant effect from the actual shot weight was also observed,
<italic>F</italic>
(4,32) = 203.37,
<italic>p</italic>
= 0.2.83e-22, η
<sup>2</sup>
= 0.96.
<italic>Post hoc</italic>
multiple comparisons using the Bonferroni correction showed significant differences (
<italic>p</italic>
s < 0.01) between all shot weights: 1 kg (
<italic>M</italic>
= 1440.5 g; SE = 110.92), 2 kg (
<italic>M</italic>
= 2140.00 g; SE = 120.04), 3 kg (
<italic>M</italic>
= 3220.00 g; SE = 140.65), 4 kg (
<italic>M</italic>
= 3890.50 g; SE = 100.10), and 5 kg (
<italic>M</italic>
= 4840.50 g; SE = 70.98). The analysis did not reveal any other significant effects. Table
<xref ref-type="table" rid="T1">1</xref>
shows the perceived weight for each actual shot from the different tasks.</p>
<table-wrap id="T1" position="float">
<label>Table 1</label>
<caption>
<p>
<bold>Mean estimation of proximal weight (SD) as a function of physical weight and task type in Experiment 2</bold>
.</p>
</caption>
<table frame="hsides" rules="groups" cellspacing="8" cellpadding="8">
<thead>
<tr>
<th align="left" rowspan="1" colspan="1"></th>
<th align="center" colspan="2" rowspan="1">Proximal weight (g)</th>
</tr>
<tr>
<th align="left" rowspan="1" colspan="1">Physical weight (kg)</th>
<th align="center" rowspan="1" colspan="1">With imagination</th>
<th align="center" rowspan="1" colspan="1">Without imagination</th>
</tr>
</thead>
<tbody>
<tr>
<td align="left" rowspan="1" colspan="1">1</td>
<td align="center" rowspan="1" colspan="1">1510 (420.80)</td>
<td align="center" rowspan="1" colspan="1">1380 (390.94)</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td align="left" rowspan="1" colspan="1">2</td>
<td align="center" rowspan="1" colspan="1">2270 (400.57)</td>
<td align="center" rowspan="1" colspan="1">2010 (380.72)</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td align="left" rowspan="1" colspan="1">3</td>
<td align="center" rowspan="1" colspan="1">3280 (460.62)</td>
<td align="center" rowspan="1" colspan="1">3160 (460.24)</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td align="left" rowspan="1" colspan="1">4</td>
<td align="center" rowspan="1" colspan="1">4100 (410.37)</td>
<td align="center" rowspan="1" colspan="1">3690 (350.73)</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td align="left" rowspan="1" colspan="1">5</td>
<td align="center" rowspan="1" colspan="1">4970 (290.08)</td>
<td align="center" rowspan="1" colspan="1">4720 (300.84)</td>
</tr>
</tbody>
</table>
</table-wrap>
<p>In Experiment 2, the participants exhibited significantly increased weight perceptions when they imagined voluntary actions accompanied by the audio aids. We did not physically manipulate the haptically perceived levels in Experiment 2; however, the perceived levels that were cognitively invited concurrently increased the proximal weight judgments. The results from Experiment 2 provide evidence for the speculation that in a given trial, the weights judged in Experiment 1 were scaled to the coordination and control action levels for that trial; the levels were cognitively rather than physically manipulated. Perception is cognition because people’s actions (e.g., running, walking, etc.) occur in their minds and in reality. Humans can use this cognition as a basis for adapting to (or better accomplishing) a task in a given environment. The concept of this ability has a clear position in oriental philosophy (see
<italic>general discussion</italic>
below).</p>
</sec>
</sec>
<sec>
<title>GENERAL DISCUSSION</title>
<p>Based on studies by
<xref rid="B11" ref-type="bibr">Fajen (2007)</xref>
,
<xref rid="B13" ref-type="bibr">Fajen et al. (2009)</xref>
,
<xref rid="B20" ref-type="bibr">Lee et al. (2012)</xref>
, and
<xref rid="B18" ref-type="bibr">Jin and Lee (2013)</xref>
, putting is an example of affordance-based control. For blind persons, the shots’ weights varied with the forms of touching, holding, weighing, and putting. The perceived weights reported by the participants were implicit reports of their “
<italic>puttability</italic>
” estimates.
<xref rid="B31" ref-type="bibr">Shockley et al. (2004)</xref>
suggested that physical dimension estimates are elliptical indications of affordances. In this study, the weights varied systematically with the masses distributed to the participants’ hands; thus, manipulation affected the hand-wielded objects’ perceived
<italic>movability</italic>
or
<italic>controllability</italic>
. Affordances might be sufficiently fundamental that they necessarily constrain weight judgments (
<xref rid="B12" ref-type="bibr">Fajen and Phillips, 2012</xref>
). Thus, heavier shots are more difficult to put than lighter shots, and accordingly, perceiving a shot’s put-to-be reflects the perception of that shot’s weight.</p>
<p>Under the traditional paradigm, affordance is nested in environment. The following question ensues: what could make the outer affordance available? A person with visual impairment may depend more on a (haptical or olfactory) perceptual system for survival than a normal individual. These individuals perceive objects not only through bodily actions but also by controlling affordance
<bold>before</bold>
the action. Improving the ability to feel and be mindful of actions can be fundamental to how one improves performance. The process is grounded in awareness: the essential tool of the mind that firmly roots it back into the body. Not only does this awareness foster a body that is free from restriction, but it also serves as a tool for calming the overactive mind. During the entire putting process, a blind man would exhibit a
<italic>puttable</italic>
effect, which may support the general thesis that affordance has an effect. As we have reiterated, if perception is cognition because people form perceptions in their minds, in reality, manipulations that affect the cognitive form should also affect weight judgments. Fatigue and muscle strength are measures of overall bodily energy, which can be considered a latent variable. One might describe the effects of neurotransmitters on this latent “bodily energy,” in contrast to focusing on molecular or cellular actions. Research shows that people’s physiological and psychosocial resources influence their visual perception (e.g.,
<xref rid="B16" ref-type="bibr">Harber et al., 2011</xref>
). This approach is similar to studies on the higher-level cognitive-emotional-physical effects of drugs such as antidepressants, the physiological actions of which are not well-understood.</p>
<p>In this study, the participants were activated by an action in which the putters’ perceived levels of coordination and control were presumably lower. In the mind, this action may have constrained the proximal weight estimates; if so, the possibility that many other manipulations, such as emotional, motivational, and procedural activation, among others, affect perception cannot be ruled out. For example, in a controversial study, participants for whom an elderly stereotype was primed walked more slowly than did control participants (
<xref rid="B2" ref-type="bibr">Bargh et al., 1996</xref>
). Our results do not robustly contribute to the argument about priming effect replicability (
<xref rid="B9" ref-type="bibr">Doyen et al., 2012</xref>
;
<xref rid="B41" ref-type="bibr">Yong, 2012</xref>
). Paraphrasing
<italic>imagination</italic>
in the present study, manipulations that only affect perceived levels of coordination and control also affect the judgments of proximal targets, goals, or objects, which provides organisms with affordances that suggest that the proximal weights judged were intrinsically scaled to the current perceptual systems (e.g., haptic and auditory). This suggestion is somewhat consistent with the study by
<xref rid="B19" ref-type="bibr">Lee and Schnall (2014)</xref>
, although it demonstrates that power, which drives potential strategies for gaining resources, can affect perception; people see the physical world as reflecting the difficulties posed by their lack of potential actions.</p>
<p>Many people experience the relationship between judging the “actable-ness” of a target and performance when the form is correct and they perform well. However, in empirical studies, differences or changes in perception observed under conditions without external behavior may be considered behavioral information and may be used to assess participants’ effects on behavior. Similar to the aforementioned blind person’s special survival skills, normal people who are well-trained are more apt to perceive the actable-ness of an object for better performance (e.g.,
<xref rid="B20" ref-type="bibr">Lee et al., 2012</xref>
; Experiment 1) because they can adjust their perceptual systems to control the affordances and obtain high levels of perception. Deliberately sensing the body brings people directly into contact with the present moment, which trains the mind to focus as if on automatic pilot. Modern neuroscience literature suggests that this trained “presence” actually builds new neural pathways within the brain and is akin to the highly prized “zone” (
<xref rid="B27" ref-type="bibr">Robinson, 2004</xref>
) that top athletes enter when they are in good form. The findings in this study also share some similarities with various “mindfulness” practices that are fashionable at the moment. People can manipulate perceived performance levels in a given environment, and this ability might render outer affordance available.</p>
<p>Behavior is traditionally considered a means to control the environment, but this view ignores the fact that an object can be perceived through action. People sit after they confirm the distance between a table and a bench; people may also first sit down and then reevaluate or adjust their distance. Although the initial stimulus is always perception, the interaction continues back and forth between perception and action. Biological studies have found that self-generated sensations are attenuated by a predictive mechanism and suggest that the nervous system’s ability to predict an action’s sensory consequences may be used for other mechanisms in addition to its role in sensory attenuation (e.g.,
<xref rid="B3" ref-type="bibr">Bays et al., 2006</xref>
). Our ability to mentally rehearse movements before performing them may be attributable to this type of prediction. Cognition guides behaviors that acquire the perceptions necessary for new behaviors. The two behaviors before and after the cognitive process (e.g., reappraisal) communicate environmental information.
<xref rid="B14" ref-type="bibr">Gibson (1979)</xref>
conceptualized this information as
<italic>survival-related symbols</italic>
given by the environment to an organism. Post-Gibson researchers have also advocated the notion that affordances are dispositional
<italic>symbols</italic>
of physical objects that necessarily actualize related actions under appropriate circumstances (e.g.,
<xref rid="B6" ref-type="bibr">Caiani, 2014</xref>
). The concept of survival is similar to that of
<italic>Chi</italic>
energy (are also known as
<italic>Kih</italic>
paradigm) in oriental philosophy (
<xref rid="B21" ref-type="bibr">Lee et al., 2007</xref>
;
<xref rid="B18" ref-type="bibr">Jin and Lee, 2013</xref>
), which defines affordance-control ability. Since ecological account showed
<italic>direct perception</italic>
and denied the need for any internal processing of biologically relevant cues to perceive meaningful affordances, it seemed to offer nothing to the analytically oriented cognitive science (e.g.,
<xref rid="B34" ref-type="bibr">Ullman, 1981</xref>
). Coordination and control are not only external actions but also level variables of internal affordance-control ability.</p>
<p>It may be difficult to explore to a larger extent what demands might be required for more successful performances. In this study, people may have perceived that the shots were heavier if their
<italic>Chi</italic>
had been energetic. Action is not only external but also internal; it even exists in a mental form, the mental processes for which may be regarded as a level of the
<italic>Chi</italic>
variable.
<italic>Chi</italic>
paradigm is more like a general theoretical framework that claims a bodily experience; action is the basis for making physical judgments and likely underlies all other basic cognitive interpretations of sensory stimuli. This goes hand in hand with the biofunctional understanding which assume direct experience of the integrated wholeness of one’s body is fundamental for developing other kinds of awareness (e.g.,
<xref rid="B28" ref-type="bibr">Rosch, 1999</xref>
). Specifically, the basis for perceptions may be understood in biofunctionalism which approaches the body as a dynamical system seen in their functional, rather than anatomical capacity, even at the sublevel (e.g., a bodily organ such like brain,
<xref rid="B17" ref-type="bibr">Iran-Nejad, 2000</xref>
). It appears that we cannot help separating mind from body in Western philosophical dogma. In order to understand the integrated nature of the mind and body, we must recognize that the mind, as a function of the brain, is essentially embodied. If we approach the mind and body as an integrated unit, we cannot separate training our muscles from our mental activity because they are unavoidably linked. Training the body perceptively necessitates quietening and training the mind as it actively engages in its observant and embodied nature.
<italic>Chi</italic>
paradigm offers a potential analytic approach to capture the intuition of wholeness in terms of biofunctionalism within the cognitive sciences.</p>
<sec>
<title>Conflict of Interest Statement</title>
<p>The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.</p>
</sec>
</sec>
</body>
<back>
<ack>
<title>ACKNOWLEDGMENT</title>
<p>This study was supported by University of California, Davis Open Access Fund (to Zheng Jin). This study was partially supported by the China Scholarship Council (CSC).</p>
</ack>
<ref-list>
<title>REFERENCES</title>
<ref id="B1">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Ashby</surname>
<given-names>F. G.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Townsend</surname>
<given-names>J. T.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>1986</year>
).
<article-title>Varieties of perceptual independence</article-title>
.
<source>Psychol. Rev.</source>
<volume>93</volume>
,
<fpage>154</fpage>
<lpage>179</lpage>
.
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1037/0033-295X.93.2.154</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">3714926</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B2">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Bargh</surname>
<given-names>J. A.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Chen</surname>
<given-names>M.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Burrows</surname>
<given-names>L.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>1996</year>
).
<article-title>Automaticity of social behavior: direct effects of trait construct and stereotype activation on action</article-title>
.
<source>J. Pers. Soc. Psychol.</source>
<volume>71</volume>
,
<fpage>230</fpage>
<lpage>244</lpage>
.
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1037/0022-3514.71.2.230</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">8765481</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B3">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Bays</surname>
<given-names>P. M.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Flanagan</surname>
<given-names>J. R.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Wolpert</surname>
<given-names>D. M.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2006</year>
).
<article-title>Attenuation of self-generated tactile sensations is predictive, not postdictive</article-title>
.
<source>PLoS Biol.</source>
<volume>4</volume>
:
<fpage>e28</fpage>
.
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1371/journal.pbio.0040028</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">16402860</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B4">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Bhalla</surname>
<given-names>M.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Proffitt</surname>
<given-names>D. R.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>1999</year>
).
<article-title>Visual-motor recalibration in geographical slant perception</article-title>
.
<source>J. Exp. Psychol. Hum. Percept. Perform.</source>
<volume>25</volume>
,
<fpage>1076</fpage>
<lpage>1096</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1037/0096-1523.25.4.1076</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">10464946</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B5">
<mixed-citation publication-type="book">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Brown</surname>
<given-names>K. W.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Cordon</surname>
<given-names>S.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2009</year>
).
<article-title>“Toward a phenomenology of mindfulness: subjective experience and emotional correlates,”</article-title>
in
<source>Clinical Handbook of Mindfulness</source>
, ed.
<person-group person-group-type="editor">
<name>
<surname>Didonna</surname>
<given-names>F.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<publisher-loc>New York</publisher-loc>
:
<publisher-name>Springer</publisher-name>
),
<fpage>59</fpage>
<lpage>81</lpage>
.</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B6">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Caiani</surname>
<given-names>S. Z.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2014</year>
).
<article-title>Extending the notion of affordance</article-title>
.
<source>Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci.</source>
<volume>13</volume>
,
<fpage>275</fpage>
<lpage>293</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1007/s11097-013-9295-1</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B7">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Cañal-Bruland</surname>
<given-names>R.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>van der Kamp</surname>
<given-names>J.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2009</year>
).
<article-title>Action goals influence action-specific perception</article-title>
.
<source>Psychon. Bull. Rev.</source>
<volume>16</volume>
,
<fpage>1100</fpage>
<lpage>1105</lpage>
.
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.3758/PBR.16.6.1100</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">19966262</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B8">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Carlson</surname>
<given-names>V. R.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>1960</year>
).
<article-title>Overestimation in size constancy judgments</article-title>
.
<source>Am. J. Psychol.</source>
<volume>73</volume>
,
<fpage>199</fpage>
<lpage>213</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.2307/1419897</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B9">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Doyen</surname>
<given-names>S.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Klein</surname>
<given-names>O.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Pichon</surname>
<given-names>C. L.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Cleeremans</surname>
<given-names>A.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2012</year>
).
<article-title>Behavioral priming: it’s all in the mind, but whose mind?</article-title>
<source>PLoS ONE</source>
<volume>7</volume>
:
<fpage>e29081</fpage>
.
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1371/journal.pone.0029081</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">22279526</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B10">
<mixed-citation publication-type="book">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Ellis</surname>
<given-names>B.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2001</year>
).
<source>Scientific Essentialism (Cambridge Studies in Philosophy)</source>
.
<publisher-loc>Cambridge</publisher-loc>
:
<publisher-name>Cambridge University Press</publisher-name>
.</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B11">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Fajen</surname>
<given-names>B. R.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2007</year>
).
<article-title>Affordance-basedcontrol of visually guided action</article-title>
.
<source>Ecol. Psychol.</source>
<volume>19</volume>
,
<fpage>383</fpage>
<lpage>410</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1080/10407410701557877</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B12">
<mixed-citation publication-type="book">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Fajen</surname>
<given-names>B. R.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Phillips</surname>
<given-names>F.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2012</year>
).
<article-title>“Spatial perception and action,”</article-title>
in
<source>Handbook of Spatial Cognition</source>
, eds
<person-group person-group-type="editor">
<name>
<surname>Waller</surname>
<given-names>D. A.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Nadel</surname>
<given-names>L.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<publisher-loc>Washington, DC</publisher-loc>
:
<publisher-name>American Psychological Association</publisher-name>
),
<fpage>67</fpage>
<lpage>80</lpage>
.</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B13">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Fajen</surname>
<given-names>B. R.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Riley</surname>
<given-names>M. R.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Turvey</surname>
<given-names>M. T.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2009</year>
).
<article-title>Information, affordances and control of action in sports</article-title>
.
<source>Int. J. Sport Psychol.</source>
<volume>40</volume>
,
<fpage>79</fpage>
<lpage>107</lpage>
.</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B14">
<mixed-citation publication-type="book">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Gibson</surname>
<given-names>J. J.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>1979</year>
).
<source>The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception</source>
.
<publisher-loc>Boston</publisher-loc>
:
<publisher-name>Houghton-Mifflin</publisher-name>
.</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B15">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Grezes</surname>
<given-names>J.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Decety</surname>
<given-names>J.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2001</year>
).
<article-title>Functional anatomy of execution, mental simulation, observation, and verb generation of actions: a meta-analysis</article-title>
.
<source>Hum. Brain Mapp.</source>
<volume>12</volume>
,
<fpage>1</fpage>
<lpage>19</lpage>
.
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">11198101</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B16">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Harber</surname>
<given-names>K.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Yeung</surname>
<given-names>D.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Iacovelli</surname>
<given-names>A.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2011</year>
).
<article-title>Psychosocial resources, threat and the perception of distance, and height: support for the resources, and perception model</article-title>
.
<source>Emotion</source>
<volume>11</volume>
,
<fpage>1080</fpage>
<lpage>1090</lpage>
.
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1037/a0023995</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">21707147</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B17">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Iran-Nejad</surname>
<given-names>A.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2000</year>
).
<article-title>Knowledge, self-regulation, and the brain-mind cycle of reflection</article-title>
.
<source>J. Mind Behav.</source>
<volume>21</volume>
,
<fpage>67</fpage>
<lpage>88</lpage>
.</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B18">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Jin</surname>
<given-names>Z.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Lee</surname>
<given-names>Y.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2013</year>
).
<article-title>Enlargement of perceived target size: intentional or natural?</article-title>
<source>Percept. Mot. Skills</source>
<volume>117</volume>
,
<fpage>855</fpage>
<lpage>867</lpage>
.
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.2466/24.27.PMS.117x26z0</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">24665802</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B19">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Lee</surname>
<given-names>E. H.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Schnall</surname>
<given-names>S.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2014</year>
).
<article-title>The influence of social power on weight perception</article-title>
.
<source>J. Exp. Psychol. Gen.</source>
<volume>143</volume>
,
<fpage>1719</fpage>
<lpage>1725</lpage>
.
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1037/a0035699</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">24490846</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B20">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Lee</surname>
<given-names>Y.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Lee</surname>
<given-names>S.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Carello</surname>
<given-names>C.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Turvey</surname>
<given-names>M. T.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2012</year>
).
<article-title>An archer’s perceived form scales the “hitableness” of archery targets</article-title>
.
<source>J. Exp. Psychol. Hum Percept. Perform.</source>
<volume>38</volume>
,
<fpage>1125</fpage>
<lpage>1131</lpage>
.
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1037/a0029036</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">22731994</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B21">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Lee</surname>
<given-names>Y.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Park</surname>
<given-names>H.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Ko</surname>
<given-names>J.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Shin</surname>
<given-names>K.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Lee</surname>
<given-names>N.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Shaw</surname>
<given-names>R.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2007</year>
).
<article-title>Issues on Kih in psychology</article-title>
.
<source>Korean J. Psychol.</source>
<volume>26</volume>
,
<fpage>63</fpage>
<lpage>83</lpage>
.</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B22">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Miller</surname>
<given-names>G.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2007</year>
).
<article-title>Reconciling evolutionary psychology and ecological psychology: how to perceive fitness affordances</article-title>
.
<source>Acta Psychol. Sin.</source>
<volume>39</volume>
,
<fpage>546</fpage>
<lpage>555</lpage>
.</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B23">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Millikan</surname>
<given-names>R. G.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>1999</year>
).
<article-title>Historical kinds and the special sciences</article-title>
.
<source>Philos. Stud.</source>
<volume>95</volume>
,
<fpage>45</fpage>
<lpage>65</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1023/A:1004532016219</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B24">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Oberle</surname>
<given-names>C. D.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Amazeen</surname>
<given-names>E. L.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2003</year>
).
<article-title>Independence and separability of volume and mass in the size-weight illusion</article-title>
.
<source>Percept. Psychophys.</source>
<volume>65</volume>
,
<fpage>831</fpage>
<lpage>843</lpage>
.
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.3758/BF03194818</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">14528894</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B25">
<mixed-citation publication-type="book">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Proffitt</surname>
<given-names>D. R.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Linkenauger</surname>
<given-names>S. A.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2013</year>
).
<article-title>“Perception viewed as a phenotypic expression,”</article-title>
in
<source>Action Science: Foundations of an Emerging Discipline</source>
, eds
<person-group person-group-type="editor">
<name>
<surname>Prinz</surname>
<given-names>W.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Beisert</surname>
<given-names>M.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Herwig</surname>
<given-names>A.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<publisher-loc>Cambridge, MA</publisher-loc>
:
<publisher-name>MIT Press</publisher-name>
),
<fpage>171</fpage>
<lpage>197</lpage>
.</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B26">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Proffitt</surname>
<given-names>D. R.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Stefanucci</surname>
<given-names>J. K.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Banton</surname>
<given-names>T.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Epstein</surname>
<given-names>W.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2003</year>
).
<article-title>The role of effort in perceiving distance</article-title>
.
<source>Psychol. Sci.</source>
<volume>14</volume>
,
<fpage>106</fpage>
<lpage>112</lpage>
.
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1111/1467-9280.t01-1-01427</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">12661670</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B27">
<mixed-citation publication-type="book">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Robinson</surname>
<given-names>P.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2004</year>
).
<article-title>“Decision support, complexity and primary healthcare,”</article-title>
in
<source>Complexity for Clinicians</source>
, ed.
<person-group person-group-type="editor">
<name>
<surname>Holt</surname>
<given-names>T. A.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<publisher-loc>Oxford</publisher-loc>
:
<publisher-name>Radcliff Publishing</publisher-name>
),
<fpage>67</fpage>
<lpage>80</lpage>
.</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B28">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Rosch</surname>
<given-names>E.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>1999</year>
).
<article-title>Is wisdom in the brain?</article-title>
<source>Psychol. Sci.</source>
<volume>10</volume>
,
<fpage>222</fpage>
<lpage>224</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1111/1467-9280.00140</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B29">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Rosch</surname>
<given-names>E.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2000</year>
).
<article-title>The brain between two paradigms: can biofunctionalism join wisdom intuitions to analytic science?</article-title>
<source>J. Mind Behav.</source>
<volume>21</volume>
,
<fpage>189</fpage>
<lpage>204</lpage>
.</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B30">
<mixed-citation publication-type="book">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Shapiro</surname>
<given-names>L. A.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2011</year>
).
<source>Embodied Cognition</source>
.
<publisher-loc>London</publisher-loc>
:
<publisher-name>Routledge</publisher-name>
.</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B31">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Shockley</surname>
<given-names>K.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Carello</surname>
<given-names>C.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Turvey</surname>
<given-names>M. T.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2004</year>
).
<article-title>Metamers in the haptic perception of heaviness and moveable-ness</article-title>
.
<source>Percept. Psychophys.</source>
<volume>66</volume>
,
<fpage>731</fpage>
<lpage>742</lpage>
.
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.3758/BF03194968</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">15495899</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B32">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Turvey</surname>
<given-names>M. T.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>1992</year>
).
<article-title>Affordances and prospective control: an outline of the ontology</article-title>
.
<source>Ecol. Psychol.</source>
<volume>4</volume>
,
<fpage>173</fpage>
<lpage>187</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1207/s15326969eco0403_3</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B33">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Turvey</surname>
<given-names>M. T.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Carello</surname>
<given-names>C.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2011</year>
).
<article-title>Obtaining information by dynamic (effortful) touching</article-title>
.
<source>Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci.</source>
<volume>366</volume>
,
<fpage>3123</fpage>
<lpage>3132</lpage>
.
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1098/rstb.2011.0159</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">21969694</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B34">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Ullman</surname>
<given-names>S.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>1981</year>
).
<article-title>Against direct perception</article-title>
.
<source>Behav. Brain Sci.</source>
<volume>3</volume>
,
<fpage>373</fpage>
<lpage>415</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1017/S0140525X0000546X</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B35">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Witt</surname>
<given-names>J. K.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2011</year>
).
<article-title>Action’s effect on perception</article-title>
.
<source>Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci.</source>
<volume>20</volume>
,
<fpage>201</fpage>
<lpage>206</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1177/0963721411408770</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B36">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Witt</surname>
<given-names>J. K.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Dorsch</surname>
<given-names>T.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2009</year>
).
<article-title>Kicking to bigger uprights: field goal kicking performance influences perceived size</article-title>
.
<source>Perception</source>
<volume>38</volume>
,
<fpage>1328</fpage>
<lpage>1340</lpage>
.
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1068/p6325</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">19911630</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B37">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Witt</surname>
<given-names>J. K.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Linkenauger</surname>
<given-names>S. A.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Bakdash</surname>
<given-names>J. Z.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Proffitt</surname>
<given-names>D. R.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2008</year>
).
<article-title>Putting to a bigger hole: golf performance relates to perceived size</article-title>
.
<source>Psychon. Bull. Rev.</source>
<volume>15</volume>
,
<fpage>581</fpage>
<lpage>585</lpage>
.
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.3758/PBR.15.3.581</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">18567258</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B38">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Witt</surname>
<given-names>J. K.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Proffitt</surname>
<given-names>D. R.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2005</year>
).
<article-title>See the ball, hit the ball: apparent ball size is correlated with batting average</article-title>
.
<source>Psychol. Sci.</source>
<volume>16</volume>
,
<fpage>937</fpage>
<lpage>938</lpage>
.
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1111/j.1467-9280.2005.01640.x</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">16313656</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B39">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Witt</surname>
<given-names>J. K.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Proffitt</surname>
<given-names>D. R.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Epstein</surname>
<given-names>W.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2010</year>
).
<article-title>When and how are spatial perceptions scaled?</article-title>
<source>J. Exp. Psychol. Hum. Percept. Perform.</source>
<volume>36</volume>
,
<fpage>1153</fpage>
<lpage>1160</lpage>
.
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1037/a0019947</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">20731519</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B40">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Witt</surname>
<given-names>J. K.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Sugovic</surname>
<given-names>M.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2013</year>
).
<article-title>Spiders appear to move faster than non-threatening objects regardless of one’s ability to block them</article-title>
.
<source>Acta Psychol.</source>
<volume>143</volume>
,
<fpage>284</fpage>
<lpage>291</lpage>
.
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1016/j.actpsy.2013.04.011</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">23692998</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="B41">
<mixed-citation publication-type="journal">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Yong</surname>
<given-names>E.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
(
<year>2012</year>
).
<article-title>Replication studies: bad copy</article-title>
.
<source>Nature</source>
<volume>485</volume>
,
<fpage>7398</fpage>
.
<pub-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1038/485298a</pub-id>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">22596136</pub-id>
</mixed-citation>
</ref>
</ref-list>
</back>
</pmc>
<affiliations>
<list>
<country>
<li>Corée du Sud</li>
<li>République populaire de Chine</li>
<li>États-Unis</li>
</country>
</list>
<tree>
<country name="République populaire de Chine">
<noRegion>
<name sortKey="Jin, Zheng" sort="Jin, Zheng" uniqKey="Jin Z" first="Zheng" last="Jin">Zheng Jin</name>
</noRegion>
<name sortKey="Zhu, Jin" sort="Zhu, Jin" uniqKey="Zhu J" first="Jin" last="Zhu">Jin Zhu</name>
</country>
<country name="États-Unis">
<noRegion>
<name sortKey="Jin, Zheng" sort="Jin, Zheng" uniqKey="Jin Z" first="Zheng" last="Jin">Zheng Jin</name>
</noRegion>
<name sortKey="Lee, Yang" sort="Lee, Yang" uniqKey="Lee Y" first="Yang" last="Lee">Yang Lee</name>
</country>
<country name="Corée du Sud">
<noRegion>
<name sortKey="Lee, Yang" sort="Lee, Yang" uniqKey="Lee Y" first="Yang" last="Lee">Yang Lee</name>
</noRegion>
</country>
</tree>
</affiliations>
</record>

Pour manipuler ce document sous Unix (Dilib)

EXPLOR_STEP=$WICRI_ROOT/Ticri/CIDE/explor/HapticV1/Data/Pmc/Checkpoint
HfdSelect -h $EXPLOR_STEP/biblio.hfd -nk 000671 | SxmlIndent | more

Ou

HfdSelect -h $EXPLOR_AREA/Data/Pmc/Checkpoint/biblio.hfd -nk 000671 | SxmlIndent | more

Pour mettre un lien sur cette page dans le réseau Wicri

{{Explor lien
   |wiki=    Ticri/CIDE
   |area=    HapticV1
   |flux=    Pmc
   |étape=   Checkpoint
   |type=    RBID
   |clé=     PMC:4330679
   |texte=   Control your mind, make affordance available
}}

Pour générer des pages wiki

HfdIndexSelect -h $EXPLOR_AREA/Data/Pmc/Checkpoint/RBID.i   -Sk "pubmed:25741298" \
       | HfdSelect -Kh $EXPLOR_AREA/Data/Pmc/Checkpoint/biblio.hfd   \
       | NlmPubMed2Wicri -a HapticV1 

Wicri

This area was generated with Dilib version V0.6.23.
Data generation: Mon Jun 13 01:09:46 2016. Site generation: Wed Mar 6 09:54:07 2024