Serveur d'exploration sur les dispositifs haptiques

Attention, ce site est en cours de développement !
Attention, site généré par des moyens informatiques à partir de corpus bruts.
Les informations ne sont donc pas validées.

Supra-personal cognitive control and metacognition

Identifieur interne : 002D43 ( Ncbi/Merge ); précédent : 002D42; suivant : 002D44

Supra-personal cognitive control and metacognition

Auteurs : Nicholas Shea [Royaume-Uni] ; Annika Boldt [Royaume-Uni] ; Dan Bang [Royaume-Uni, Danemark] ; Nick Yeung [Royaume-Uni] ; Cecilia Heyes [Royaume-Uni] ; Chris D. Frith [Danemark, Royaume-Uni]

Source :

RBID : PMC:3989995

Abstract

Highlights

We propose a ‘dual systems’ framework for thinking about metacognition.

System 1 metacognition is for ‘intra-personal’ cognitive control.

System 2 metacognition is for ‘supra-personal’ cognitive control.

The latter allows agents to share metacognitive representations.

This sharing creates benefits for the group and facilitates cumulative culture.


Url:
DOI: 10.1016/j.tics.2014.01.006
PubMed: 24582436
PubMed Central: 3989995

Links toward previous steps (curation, corpus...)


Links to Exploration step

PMC:3989995

Le document en format XML

<record>
<TEI>
<teiHeader>
<fileDesc>
<titleStmt>
<title xml:lang="en">Supra-personal cognitive control and metacognition</title>
<author>
<name sortKey="Shea, Nicholas" sort="Shea, Nicholas" uniqKey="Shea N" first="Nicholas" last="Shea">Nicholas Shea</name>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff0005">Department of Philosophy, King's College London, Strand, London WC2R 2LS, UK</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">Royaume-Uni</country>
<wicri:regionArea>Department of Philosophy, King's College London, Strand, London WC2R 2LS</wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:noRegion>London WC2R 2LS</wicri:noRegion>
</affiliation>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Boldt, Annika" sort="Boldt, Annika" uniqKey="Boldt A" first="Annika" last="Boldt">Annika Boldt</name>
<affiliation wicri:level="4">
<nlm:aff id="aff0010">Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, South Parks Road, Oxford, OX1 3UD, UK</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">Royaume-Uni</country>
<wicri:regionArea>Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, South Parks Road, Oxford, OX1 3UD</wicri:regionArea>
<orgName type="university">Université d'Oxford</orgName>
<placeName>
<settlement type="city">Oxford</settlement>
<region type="nation">Angleterre</region>
<region type="région" nuts="1">Oxfordshire</region>
</placeName>
</affiliation>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Bang, Dan" sort="Bang, Dan" uniqKey="Bang D" first="Dan" last="Bang">Dan Bang</name>
<affiliation wicri:level="4">
<nlm:aff id="aff0010">Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, South Parks Road, Oxford, OX1 3UD, UK</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">Royaume-Uni</country>
<wicri:regionArea>Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, South Parks Road, Oxford, OX1 3UD</wicri:regionArea>
<orgName type="university">Université d'Oxford</orgName>
<placeName>
<settlement type="city">Oxford</settlement>
<region type="nation">Angleterre</region>
<region type="région" nuts="1">Oxfordshire</region>
</placeName>
</affiliation>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff0015">Calleva Research Centre for Evolution and Human Sciences, Magdalen College, High Street, Oxford OX1 4AU, UK</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">Royaume-Uni</country>
<wicri:regionArea>Calleva Research Centre for Evolution and Human Sciences, Magdalen College, High Street, Oxford OX1 4AU</wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:noRegion>Oxford OX1 4AU</wicri:noRegion>
</affiliation>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff0020">Interacting Minds Centre, Aarhus University, Jens Chr. Skous Vej 4, Building 1483, 8000 Aarhus, Denmark</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">Danemark</country>
<wicri:regionArea>Interacting Minds Centre, Aarhus University, Jens Chr. Skous Vej 4, Building 1483, 8000 Aarhus</wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:noRegion>8000 Aarhus</wicri:noRegion>
</affiliation>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Yeung, Nick" sort="Yeung, Nick" uniqKey="Yeung N" first="Nick" last="Yeung">Nick Yeung</name>
<affiliation wicri:level="4">
<nlm:aff id="aff0010">Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, South Parks Road, Oxford, OX1 3UD, UK</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">Royaume-Uni</country>
<wicri:regionArea>Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, South Parks Road, Oxford, OX1 3UD</wicri:regionArea>
<orgName type="university">Université d'Oxford</orgName>
<placeName>
<settlement type="city">Oxford</settlement>
<region type="nation">Angleterre</region>
<region type="région" nuts="1">Oxfordshire</region>
</placeName>
</affiliation>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Heyes, Cecilia" sort="Heyes, Cecilia" uniqKey="Heyes C" first="Cecilia" last="Heyes">Cecilia Heyes</name>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff0025">All Souls College, High Street, Oxford OX1 4AL, UK</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">Royaume-Uni</country>
<wicri:regionArea>All Souls College, High Street, Oxford OX1 4AL</wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:noRegion>Oxford OX1 4AL</wicri:noRegion>
</affiliation>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Frith, Chris D" sort="Frith, Chris D" uniqKey="Frith C" first="Chris D." last="Frith">Chris D. Frith</name>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff0020">Interacting Minds Centre, Aarhus University, Jens Chr. Skous Vej 4, Building 1483, 8000 Aarhus, Denmark</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">Danemark</country>
<wicri:regionArea>Interacting Minds Centre, Aarhus University, Jens Chr. Skous Vej 4, Building 1483, 8000 Aarhus</wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:noRegion>8000 Aarhus</wicri:noRegion>
</affiliation>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff0030">Wellcome Trust Centre for NeuroImaging at UCL, 12 Queen Square, London WC1N 3BG, UK</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">Royaume-Uni</country>
<wicri:regionArea>Wellcome Trust Centre for NeuroImaging at UCL, 12 Queen Square, London WC1N 3BG</wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:noRegion>London WC1N 3BG</wicri:noRegion>
</affiliation>
</author>
</titleStmt>
<publicationStmt>
<idno type="wicri:source">PMC</idno>
<idno type="pmid">24582436</idno>
<idno type="pmc">3989995</idno>
<idno type="url">http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3989995</idno>
<idno type="RBID">PMC:3989995</idno>
<idno type="doi">10.1016/j.tics.2014.01.006</idno>
<date when="2014">2014</date>
<idno type="wicri:Area/Pmc/Corpus">002821</idno>
<idno type="wicri:Area/Pmc/Curation">002821</idno>
<idno type="wicri:Area/Pmc/Checkpoint">000930</idno>
<idno type="wicri:Area/Ncbi/Merge">002D43</idno>
</publicationStmt>
<sourceDesc>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<title xml:lang="en" level="a" type="main">Supra-personal cognitive control and metacognition</title>
<author>
<name sortKey="Shea, Nicholas" sort="Shea, Nicholas" uniqKey="Shea N" first="Nicholas" last="Shea">Nicholas Shea</name>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff0005">Department of Philosophy, King's College London, Strand, London WC2R 2LS, UK</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">Royaume-Uni</country>
<wicri:regionArea>Department of Philosophy, King's College London, Strand, London WC2R 2LS</wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:noRegion>London WC2R 2LS</wicri:noRegion>
</affiliation>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Boldt, Annika" sort="Boldt, Annika" uniqKey="Boldt A" first="Annika" last="Boldt">Annika Boldt</name>
<affiliation wicri:level="4">
<nlm:aff id="aff0010">Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, South Parks Road, Oxford, OX1 3UD, UK</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">Royaume-Uni</country>
<wicri:regionArea>Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, South Parks Road, Oxford, OX1 3UD</wicri:regionArea>
<orgName type="university">Université d'Oxford</orgName>
<placeName>
<settlement type="city">Oxford</settlement>
<region type="nation">Angleterre</region>
<region type="région" nuts="1">Oxfordshire</region>
</placeName>
</affiliation>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Bang, Dan" sort="Bang, Dan" uniqKey="Bang D" first="Dan" last="Bang">Dan Bang</name>
<affiliation wicri:level="4">
<nlm:aff id="aff0010">Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, South Parks Road, Oxford, OX1 3UD, UK</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">Royaume-Uni</country>
<wicri:regionArea>Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, South Parks Road, Oxford, OX1 3UD</wicri:regionArea>
<orgName type="university">Université d'Oxford</orgName>
<placeName>
<settlement type="city">Oxford</settlement>
<region type="nation">Angleterre</region>
<region type="région" nuts="1">Oxfordshire</region>
</placeName>
</affiliation>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff0015">Calleva Research Centre for Evolution and Human Sciences, Magdalen College, High Street, Oxford OX1 4AU, UK</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">Royaume-Uni</country>
<wicri:regionArea>Calleva Research Centre for Evolution and Human Sciences, Magdalen College, High Street, Oxford OX1 4AU</wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:noRegion>Oxford OX1 4AU</wicri:noRegion>
</affiliation>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff0020">Interacting Minds Centre, Aarhus University, Jens Chr. Skous Vej 4, Building 1483, 8000 Aarhus, Denmark</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">Danemark</country>
<wicri:regionArea>Interacting Minds Centre, Aarhus University, Jens Chr. Skous Vej 4, Building 1483, 8000 Aarhus</wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:noRegion>8000 Aarhus</wicri:noRegion>
</affiliation>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Yeung, Nick" sort="Yeung, Nick" uniqKey="Yeung N" first="Nick" last="Yeung">Nick Yeung</name>
<affiliation wicri:level="4">
<nlm:aff id="aff0010">Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, South Parks Road, Oxford, OX1 3UD, UK</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">Royaume-Uni</country>
<wicri:regionArea>Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, South Parks Road, Oxford, OX1 3UD</wicri:regionArea>
<orgName type="university">Université d'Oxford</orgName>
<placeName>
<settlement type="city">Oxford</settlement>
<region type="nation">Angleterre</region>
<region type="région" nuts="1">Oxfordshire</region>
</placeName>
</affiliation>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Heyes, Cecilia" sort="Heyes, Cecilia" uniqKey="Heyes C" first="Cecilia" last="Heyes">Cecilia Heyes</name>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff0025">All Souls College, High Street, Oxford OX1 4AL, UK</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">Royaume-Uni</country>
<wicri:regionArea>All Souls College, High Street, Oxford OX1 4AL</wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:noRegion>Oxford OX1 4AL</wicri:noRegion>
</affiliation>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Frith, Chris D" sort="Frith, Chris D" uniqKey="Frith C" first="Chris D." last="Frith">Chris D. Frith</name>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff0020">Interacting Minds Centre, Aarhus University, Jens Chr. Skous Vej 4, Building 1483, 8000 Aarhus, Denmark</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">Danemark</country>
<wicri:regionArea>Interacting Minds Centre, Aarhus University, Jens Chr. Skous Vej 4, Building 1483, 8000 Aarhus</wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:noRegion>8000 Aarhus</wicri:noRegion>
</affiliation>
<affiliation wicri:level="1">
<nlm:aff id="aff0030">Wellcome Trust Centre for NeuroImaging at UCL, 12 Queen Square, London WC1N 3BG, UK</nlm:aff>
<country xml:lang="fr">Royaume-Uni</country>
<wicri:regionArea>Wellcome Trust Centre for NeuroImaging at UCL, 12 Queen Square, London WC1N 3BG</wicri:regionArea>
<wicri:noRegion>London WC1N 3BG</wicri:noRegion>
</affiliation>
</author>
</analytic>
<series>
<title level="j">Trends in Cognitive Sciences</title>
<idno type="ISSN">1364-6613</idno>
<idno type="eISSN">1879-307X</idno>
<imprint>
<date when="2014">2014</date>
</imprint>
</series>
</biblStruct>
</sourceDesc>
</fileDesc>
<profileDesc>
<textClass></textClass>
</profileDesc>
</teiHeader>
<front>
<div type="abstract" xml:lang="en">
<title>Highlights</title>
<p>
<list list-type="simple">
<list-item id="lsti0005">
<label></label>
<p>We propose a ‘dual systems’ framework for thinking about metacognition.</p>
</list-item>
<list-item id="lsti0010">
<label></label>
<p>System 1 metacognition is for ‘intra-personal’ cognitive control.</p>
</list-item>
<list-item id="lsti0015">
<label></label>
<p>System 2 metacognition is for ‘supra-personal’ cognitive control.</p>
</list-item>
<list-item id="lsti0020">
<label></label>
<p>The latter allows agents to share metacognitive representations.</p>
</list-item>
<list-item id="lsti0025">
<label></label>
<p>This sharing creates benefits for the group and facilitates cumulative culture.</p>
</list-item>
</list>
</p>
</div>
</front>
<back>
<div1 type="bibliography">
<listBibl>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Block, N" uniqKey="Block N">N. Block</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Kahneman, D" uniqKey="Kahneman D">D. Kahneman</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Evans, J S B T" uniqKey="Evans J">J.S.B.T. Evans</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Stanovich, K E" uniqKey="Stanovich K">K.E. Stanovich</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Kiani, R" uniqKey="Kiani R">R. Kiani</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Shadlen, M N" uniqKey="Shadlen M">M.N. Shadlen</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Kepecs, A" uniqKey="Kepecs A">A. Kepecs</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Komura, Y" uniqKey="Komura Y">Y. Komura</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Terrace, H S" uniqKey="Terrace H">H.S. Terrace</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Son, L K" uniqKey="Son L">L.K. Son</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Carruthers, P" uniqKey="Carruthers P">P. Carruthers</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Metcalfe, J" uniqKey="Metcalfe J">J. Metcalfe</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Fernandez Duque, D" uniqKey="Fernandez Duque D">D. Fernandez-Duque</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Drugowitsch, J" uniqKey="Drugowitsch J">J. Drugowitsch</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Pouget, A" uniqKey="Pouget A">A. Pouget</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Ernst, M O" uniqKey="Ernst M">M.O. Ernst</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Banks, M S" uniqKey="Banks M">M.S. Banks</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Davelaar, E J" uniqKey="Davelaar E">E.J. Davelaar</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Davis, E L" uniqKey="Davis E">E.L. Davis</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Shenhav, A" uniqKey="Shenhav A">A. Shenhav</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Sakai, K" uniqKey="Sakai K">K. Sakai</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Yeung, N" uniqKey="Yeung N">N. Yeung</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Norman, D A" uniqKey="Norman D">D.A. Norman</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Shallice, T" uniqKey="Shallice T">T. Shallice</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Desimone, R" uniqKey="Desimone R">R. Desimone</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Duncan, J" uniqKey="Duncan J">J. Duncan</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Dehaene, S" uniqKey="Dehaene S">S. Dehaene</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Naccache, L" uniqKey="Naccache L">L. Naccache</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Kahneman, D" uniqKey="Kahneman D">D. Kahneman</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Sumner, P" uniqKey="Sumner P">P. Sumner</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Custers, R" uniqKey="Custers R">R. Custers</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Aarts, H" uniqKey="Aarts H">H. Aarts</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Logan, G D" uniqKey="Logan G">G.D. Logan</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Crump, M J C" uniqKey="Crump M">M.J.C. Crump</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Naccache, L" uniqKey="Naccache L">L. Naccache</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Bach, D R" uniqKey="Bach D">D.R. Bach</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Dolan, R J" uniqKey="Dolan R">R.J. Dolan</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Summerfield, C" uniqKey="Summerfield C">C. Summerfield</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Yeung, N" uniqKey="Yeung N">N. Yeung</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Richardson, M J" uniqKey="Richardson M">M.J. Richardson</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Hasson, U" uniqKey="Hasson U">U. Hasson</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Byrne, R" uniqKey="Byrne R">R. Byrne</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Whiten, A" uniqKey="Whiten A">A. Whiten</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Herrmann, E" uniqKey="Herrmann E">E. Herrmann</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Bahrami, B" uniqKey="Bahrami B">B. Bahrami</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Fusaroli, R" uniqKey="Fusaroli R">R. Fusaroli</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Tenney, E R" uniqKey="Tenney E">E.R. Tenney</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Poizat, G" uniqKey="Poizat G">G. Poizat</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Lausic, D" uniqKey="Lausic D">D. Lausic</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Job, V" uniqKey="Job V">V. Job</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Hurks, P P M" uniqKey="Hurks P">P.P.M. Hurks</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Koriat, A" uniqKey="Koriat A">A. Koriat</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Bahrami, B" uniqKey="Bahrami B">B. Bahrami</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Payne, B D" uniqKey="Payne B">B.D. Payne</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Manning, B H" uniqKey="Manning B">B.H. Manning</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Reed, N" uniqKey="Reed N">N. Reed</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Meiser, T" uniqKey="Meiser T">T. Meiser</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Brewer, W F" uniqKey="Brewer W">W.F. Brewer</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Sampaio, C" uniqKey="Sampaio C">C. Sampaio</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Overgaard, M" uniqKey="Overgaard M">M. Overgaard</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Sandberg, K" uniqKey="Sandberg K">K. Sandberg</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Friston, K" uniqKey="Friston K">K. Friston</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Shea, N" uniqKey="Shea N">N. Shea</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Yue, C L" uniqKey="Yue C">C.L. Yue</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Chambon, V" uniqKey="Chambon V">V. Chambon</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Haggard, P" uniqKey="Haggard P">P. Haggard</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Hoffman, Y" uniqKey="Hoffman Y">Y. Hoffman</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Nardini, M" uniqKey="Nardini M">M. Nardini</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Tomasello, M" uniqKey="Tomasello M">M. Tomasello</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Sterelny, K" uniqKey="Sterelny K">K. Sterelny</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Matzel, L D" uniqKey="Matzel L">L.D. Matzel</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Kolata, S" uniqKey="Kolata S">S. Kolata</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Dickinson, A" uniqKey="Dickinson A">A. Dickinson</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Mayer, A" uniqKey="Mayer A">A. Mayer</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Tr Uble, B E" uniqKey="Tr Uble B">B.E. Träuble</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Rigoni, D" uniqKey="Rigoni D">D. Rigoni</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Pleskac, T J" uniqKey="Pleskac T">T.J. Pleskac</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Busemeyer, J R" uniqKey="Busemeyer J">J.R. Busemeyer</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Yeung, N" uniqKey="Yeung N">N. Yeung</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Summerfield, C" uniqKey="Summerfield C">C. Summerfield</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Pasquali, A" uniqKey="Pasquali A">A. Pasquali</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Smith, J D" uniqKey="Smith J">J.D. Smith</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Schwartz, B" uniqKey="Schwartz B">B. Schwartz</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Gigerenzer, G" uniqKey="Gigerenzer G">G. Gigerenzer</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Higham, P A" uniqKey="Higham P">P.A. Higham</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Peirce, C S" uniqKey="Peirce C">C.S. Peirce</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Charles, L" uniqKey="Charles L">L. Charles</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Middlebrooks, P G" uniqKey="Middlebrooks P">P.G. Middlebrooks</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Sommer, M A" uniqKey="Sommer M">M.A. Sommer</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Kepecs, A" uniqKey="Kepecs A">A. Kepecs</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Mainen, Z F" uniqKey="Mainen Z">Z.F. Mainen</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Hanks, T D" uniqKey="Hanks T">T.D. Hanks</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Moreno Bote, R" uniqKey="Moreno Bote R">R. Moreno-Bote</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Zylberberg, A" uniqKey="Zylberberg A">A. Zylberberg</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Koriat, A" uniqKey="Koriat A">A. Koriat</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Castel, A D" uniqKey="Castel A">A.D. Castel</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Hertzog, C" uniqKey="Hertzog C">C. Hertzog</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Koriat, A" uniqKey="Koriat A">A. Koriat</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Call, J" uniqKey="Call J">J. Call</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Beran, M J" uniqKey="Beran M">M.J. Beran</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Smith, J D" uniqKey="Smith J">J.D. Smith</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Foote, A L" uniqKey="Foote A">A.L. Foote</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Crystal, J D" uniqKey="Crystal J">J.D. Crystal</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Adams, A" uniqKey="Adams A">A. Adams</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Santi, A" uniqKey="Santi A">A. Santi</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Templer, V L" uniqKey="Templer V">V.L. Templer</name>
</author>
<author>
<name sortKey="Hampton, R R" uniqKey="Hampton R">R.R. Hampton</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Kornell, N" uniqKey="Kornell N">N. Kornell</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
<biblStruct>
<analytic>
<author>
<name sortKey="Le Pelley, M E" uniqKey="Le Pelley M">M.E. Le Pelley</name>
</author>
</analytic>
</biblStruct>
</listBibl>
</div1>
</back>
</TEI>
<pmc article-type="review-article">
<pmc-dir>properties open_access</pmc-dir>
<front>
<journal-meta>
<journal-id journal-id-type="nlm-ta">Trends Cogn Sci</journal-id>
<journal-id journal-id-type="iso-abbrev">Trends Cogn. Sci. (Regul. Ed.)</journal-id>
<journal-title-group>
<journal-title>Trends in Cognitive Sciences</journal-title>
</journal-title-group>
<issn pub-type="ppub">1364-6613</issn>
<issn pub-type="epub">1879-307X</issn>
<publisher>
<publisher-name>Elsevier Science</publisher-name>
</publisher>
</journal-meta>
<article-meta>
<article-id pub-id-type="pmid">24582436</article-id>
<article-id pub-id-type="pmc">3989995</article-id>
<article-id pub-id-type="publisher-id">S1364-6613(14)00023-0</article-id>
<article-id pub-id-type="doi">10.1016/j.tics.2014.01.006</article-id>
<article-categories>
<subj-group subj-group-type="heading">
<subject>Opinion</subject>
</subj-group>
</article-categories>
<title-group>
<article-title>Supra-personal cognitive control and metacognition</article-title>
</title-group>
<contrib-group>
<contrib contrib-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Shea</surname>
<given-names>Nicholas</given-names>
</name>
<xref rid="aff0005" ref-type="aff">1</xref>
</contrib>
<contrib contrib-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Boldt</surname>
<given-names>Annika</given-names>
</name>
<xref rid="aff0010" ref-type="aff">2</xref>
</contrib>
<contrib contrib-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Bang</surname>
<given-names>Dan</given-names>
</name>
<xref rid="aff0010" ref-type="aff">2</xref>
<xref rid="aff0015" ref-type="aff">3</xref>
<xref rid="aff0020" ref-type="aff">4</xref>
</contrib>
<contrib contrib-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Yeung</surname>
<given-names>Nick</given-names>
</name>
<xref rid="aff0010" ref-type="aff">2</xref>
</contrib>
<contrib contrib-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Heyes</surname>
<given-names>Cecilia</given-names>
</name>
<xref rid="aff0025" ref-type="aff">5</xref>
</contrib>
<contrib contrib-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Frith</surname>
<given-names>Chris D.</given-names>
</name>
<email>c.frith@ucl.ac.uk</email>
<xref rid="aff0020" ref-type="aff">4</xref>
<xref rid="aff0030" ref-type="aff">6</xref>
</contrib>
</contrib-group>
<aff id="aff0005">
<label>1</label>
Department of Philosophy, King's College London, Strand, London WC2R 2LS, UK</aff>
<aff id="aff0010">
<label>2</label>
Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, South Parks Road, Oxford, OX1 3UD, UK</aff>
<aff id="aff0015">
<label>3</label>
Calleva Research Centre for Evolution and Human Sciences, Magdalen College, High Street, Oxford OX1 4AU, UK</aff>
<aff id="aff0020">
<label>4</label>
Interacting Minds Centre, Aarhus University, Jens Chr. Skous Vej 4, Building 1483, 8000 Aarhus, Denmark</aff>
<aff id="aff0025">
<label>5</label>
All Souls College, High Street, Oxford OX1 4AL, UK</aff>
<aff id="aff0030">
<label>6</label>
Wellcome Trust Centre for NeuroImaging at UCL, 12 Queen Square, London WC1N 3BG, UK</aff>
<pub-date pub-type="pmc-release">
<day>1</day>
<month>4</month>
<year>2014</year>
</pub-date>
<pmc-comment> PMC Release delay is 0 months and 0 days and was based on .</pmc-comment>
<pub-date pub-type="ppub">
<month>4</month>
<year>2014</year>
</pub-date>
<volume>18</volume>
<issue>4</issue>
<fpage>186</fpage>
<lpage>193</lpage>
<permissions>
<copyright-statement>© 2014 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.</copyright-statement>
<copyright-year>2014</copyright-year>
<copyright-holder>Elsevier Ltd</copyright-holder>
</permissions>
<abstract abstract-type="author-highlights">
<title>Highlights</title>
<p>
<list list-type="simple">
<list-item id="lsti0005">
<label></label>
<p>We propose a ‘dual systems’ framework for thinking about metacognition.</p>
</list-item>
<list-item id="lsti0010">
<label></label>
<p>System 1 metacognition is for ‘intra-personal’ cognitive control.</p>
</list-item>
<list-item id="lsti0015">
<label></label>
<p>System 2 metacognition is for ‘supra-personal’ cognitive control.</p>
</list-item>
<list-item id="lsti0020">
<label></label>
<p>The latter allows agents to share metacognitive representations.</p>
</list-item>
<list-item id="lsti0025">
<label></label>
<p>This sharing creates benefits for the group and facilitates cumulative culture.</p>
</list-item>
</list>
</p>
</abstract>
<abstract>
<p>The human mind is extraordinary in its ability not merely to respond to events as they unfold but also to adapt its own operation in pursuit of its agenda. This ‘cognitive control’ can be achieved through simple interactions among sensorimotor processes, and through interactions in which one sensorimotor process represents a property of another in an implicit, unconscious way. So why does the human mind also represent properties of cognitive processes in an explicit way, enabling us to think and say ‘I’m sure’ or ‘I’m doubtful’? We suggest that ‘system 2 metacognition’ is for supra-personal cognitive control. It allows metacognitive information to be broadcast, and thereby to coordinate the sensorimotor systems of two or more agents involved in a shared task.</p>
</abstract>
</article-meta>
</front>
<body>
<sec id="sec0005">
<title>A novel framework for metacognition research</title>
<p>Converging theoretical and empirical research suggests that most animals implicitly represent properties of their cognitive processes and use these for cognitive control (see
<xref rid="glo0005" ref-type="glossary">Glossary</xref>
<xref rid="bib0005 bib0010 bib0015" ref-type="bibr">[1–3]</xref>
)
<xref rid="bib0020 bib0025 bib0030" ref-type="bibr">[4–6]</xref>
. This challenges the view that only humans have metacognition
<xref rid="bib0035" ref-type="bibr">[7]</xref>
, which is broadly defined as ‘cognition about cognition’, and raises the question why humans, unlike other animals, not only implicitly but also explicitly represent properties of their cognitive processes.</p>
<p>In this opinion article, we propose a ‘dual systems’ framework for thinking about metacognition. In our framework, metacognition is composed of a cognitively ‘lean’ system, system 1 metacognition, which operates implicitly and is for the control of processes within one agent (intra-personal cognitive control), and a cognitively ‘rich’ system, system 2 metacognition, which is likely to be unique to humans and is for the control of processes within multiple agents (supra-personal cognitive control). Whereas the former system is found in many animals, the latter system is likely to be unique to humans. Our ‘lean’ account of metacognition clarifies the minimal requirements for metacognition and thereby offers a conceptual anchor in a literature where there are many conflicting assumptions about what counts as metacognition. Further, our ‘rich’ account of metacognition addresses why humans evolved the ability to explicitly represent properties of their cognitive processes: by sharing and discussing these representations, agents can engage in novel forms of adaptive group behaviour and build cumulative culture.</p>
<sec id="sec0010">
<title>Metacognition and its relation to cognitive control</title>
<p>The broad definition of metacognition as ‘cognition about cognition’ is often interpreted widely (
<xref rid="bib0040" ref-type="bibr">[8]</xref>
, p. 170), to include any cognitive process that receives information from and has a controlling influence on another cognitive process
<xref rid="bib0045 bib0050" ref-type="bibr">[9,10]</xref>
. So-construed, metacognition would encompass every type of cognitive control. We define metacognition more narrowly, as control processes that make use of one or more metacognitive representations, that is, representations of a property of a cognitive process (
<xref rid="tb0005 tb0010" ref-type="boxed-text">Boxes 1 and 2</xref>
).</p>
<p>For example, a perceptual process may use the mean firing rate of a population of neurons in visual cortex to represent a perceived property such as the length of a line. Crucially, the variance of the firing rate across the population indicates the extent to which the neurons ‘agree’ about the line length and thus carries information about the reliability of the perceptual representation (metacognitive information)
<xref rid="bib0055" ref-type="bibr">[11]</xref>
. We propose that, if the latter type of information is used to control the relative influence of the perceptual representation on cognition
<xref rid="bib0060" ref-type="bibr">[12]</xref>
, then it counts as a metacognitive representation, and the use of this representation for cognitive control should be considered to be an instance of metacognition. As well as choosing which sensorimotor dispositions are allowed to drive behaviour, metacognition thus conceived can be involved in distributing resources between rival processes
<xref rid="bib0065" ref-type="bibr">[13]</xref>
, in emotion regulation
<xref rid="bib0070" ref-type="bibr">[14]</xref>
, in guiding memory retrieval
<xref rid="bib0045" ref-type="bibr">[9]</xref>
, allocating study time
<xref rid="bib0045" ref-type="bibr">[9]</xref>
, and so on.</p>
</sec>
<sec id="sec0015">
<title>Only some forms of cognitive control involve metacognition</title>
<p>Although all metacognition is a form of cognitive control, only some forms of cognitive control are metacognitive. Cognitive control need not make use of metacognitive representations and can be guided instead by object level representations, for example, of value or of abstract goals
<xref rid="bib0075 bib0080" ref-type="bibr">[15,16]</xref>
. By contrast, other control processes do make use of metacognitive representations, for example, they represent that mutually inconsistent actions have been activated, which prompts the use of cognitive control processes in response selection
<xref rid="bib0050 bib0085" ref-type="bibr">[10,17]</xref>
.</p>
<p>Thus, our first conclusion is that, if metacognition is defined carefully, metacognition does not encompass every type of cognitive control. What, then, is distinctive about metacognition, beyond its defining feature – the use of metacognitive representations? One possibility is that metacognition is only found in the cognitive control processes carried out by higher executive systems. In considering this possibility and suggesting an alternative, we make use of the well-known distinction between system 1 and system 2
<xref rid="bib0015" ref-type="bibr">[3]</xref>
. However, our proposal does not depend on the details of dual systems theory, and it is consistent with other theories of higher-level executive function
<xref rid="bib0090 bib0095 bib0100" ref-type="bibr">[18–20]</xref>
. The dual-systems model draws on evidence that there is a distinctive form of cognitive processing, type 2 processing or system 2, with respect to which various functional features tend to cluster together, underpinned by their reliance on a capacity-limited generalised working memory system
<xref rid="bib0010 bib0015 bib0105" ref-type="bibr">[2,3,21]</xref>
. System 2 handles problems serially, takes time to operate and is affected by general working memory load. Its effectiveness correlates with individual differences in measures of general intelligence. By contrast, system 1 processes can act quickly, with many operating autonomously in parallel, and are little affected by general working memory load. System 2 representations are characteristically explicit, that is, conscious, whereas system 1 representations need not be.</p>
<p>Are metacognitive processes simply those control processes that are carried out by system 2? Unfortunately, things do not fall out so neatly. Much cognitive control takes place outside system 2
<xref rid="bib0110 bib0115" ref-type="bibr">[22,23]</xref>
. For example, experimental subjects can inhibit responses to stimuli of which they remain unaware due to visual masking
<xref rid="bib0110" ref-type="bibr">[22]</xref>
and slow down after errors they do not know they have made
<xref rid="bib0120" ref-type="bibr">[24]</xref>
. These system 1 types of control can make use of metacognitive representations such as decision uncertainty
<xref rid="bib0125 bib0130" ref-type="bibr">[25,26]</xref>
, for example, as evident in a neuropsychological patient whose behaviour shows adaptation to the prevailing difficulty of the task even though she has no conscious experience of mental effort
<xref rid="bib0125" ref-type="bibr">[25]</xref>
. Non-human animals are similarly capable of using metacognitive information
<xref rid="bib0135" ref-type="bibr">[27]</xref>
(
<xref rid="tb0010" ref-type="boxed-text">Box 2</xref>
). That, however, leaves us with a pressing puzzle. If system 1 metacognition is so pervasive, in humans and other animals, what role is there for system 2 metacognition?</p>
</sec>
</sec>
<sec id="sec0020">
<title>A hypothesis about the distinctive function of system 2 metacognition</title>
<p>Our answer to the puzzle – what is the role of system 2 metacognition? – will be that it comes into its own when the action-driving systems to be controlled are found in two different agents: that is, in cases of ‘supra-personal cognitive control’.</p>
<p>Within a single agent, domain-general processes of learning, which are part of system 1, can quickly establish – through experience – the best way to prioritise the inputs to and outputs from competing sensorimotor systems (
<xref rid="fig0005" ref-type="fig">Figure 1</xref>
). Such processes can use system 1 metacognitive information – for example, variance of a distribution, time to completion of a process, activation of incompatible response tendencies (
<xref rid="tb0005" ref-type="boxed-text">Box 1</xref>
) – to improve those trade-offs, just as they can learn to use any other type of relevant cue. The result will be a form of control that is implemented within system 1 processing and relies on metacognitive representations – that is, a system 1 form of metacognition.</p>
<p>When sensorimotor systems have to be coordinated between two or more interacting agents it is no longer possible for learning automatically to make use of all and any metacognitive information located anywhere within the different agents: my system 1 learning processes have direct access to the metacognitive information in my head, but not to the metacognitive information in your head, and vice versa. Some forms of coordinated action do not depend on metacognitive representations, for example, bodily movements can be synchronised relying only on object level information (e.g., about the location and trajectory of limbs)
<xref rid="bib0140 bib0145" ref-type="bibr">[28,29]</xref>
. But inter-agent control will typically be more effective when it can use metacognitive representations, if relevant metacognitive representations within system 1 processes in each agent are selected for broadcast to the other agent, so that decisions about which sensorimotor processes to deploy can be taken in a space of shared metacognitive information. This, we suggest, is the distinctive role of system 2 metacognition: to select metacognitive information for broadcast, in the service of controlling the sensorimotor systems of two or more agents involved in a shared task – that is, for supra-personal cognitive control (
<xref rid="fig0010" ref-type="fig">Figure 2</xref>
).</p>
<p>Ours is different from the hypothesis that metacognition is for mentalising –that is, perceiving or inferring other people's mental states
<xref rid="bib0150 bib0155" ref-type="bibr">[30,31]</xref>
. The first difference is that the representations concern one's own cognitive processes in the first instance, rather than those of another. The second difference is that communicating metacognitive representations plays a central role. To caricature: the mentalising story says that metacognition is there to allow agent A to infer that agent B has seen a rabbit; according to us, system 2 metacognition is there to allow agent A to communicate that his visuomotor fix on the rabbit is pretty reliable at present.</p>
</sec>
<sec id="sec0025">
<title>How system 2 metacognition works</title>
<sec id="sec0030">
<title>System 2 metacognition plays a central role in group decision making</title>
<p>According to our hypothesis, system 2 metacognition should play a central role in group decision making. Indeed we find that joint perceptual decision making is significantly more effective when participants communicate metacognitive representations about the stimuli
<xref rid="bib0160 bib0165" ref-type="bibr">[32,33]</xref>
. When deciding whether to trust witness testimony, (mock) jurors make considerable use of a witness's confidence and other metacognitive representations (e.g., calibration of confidence and accuracy)
<xref rid="bib0170" ref-type="bibr">[34]</xref>
. People also communicate metacognitive representations when they are synchronically coordinating complex actions (e.g., communications about confidence used in team sports)
<xref rid="bib0175 bib0180" ref-type="bibr">[35,36]</xref>
. System 2 metacognition can also be used diachronically, for example, making it possible for people to discuss how metacognitive representations should be deployed, affecting their own cognitive control
<xref rid="bib0185" ref-type="bibr">[37]</xref>
. Control strategies based on metacognitive representations, for example, what to do when memory fails, can be the subject of explicit instruction. For example, a person can learn socially that, following failure to produce items in a verbal fluency task to name animals, a good strategy is to consider subcategories of animals (farm animals, pets, etc.)
<xref rid="bib0190" ref-type="bibr">[38]</xref>
.</p>
</sec>
<sec id="sec0035">
<title>Three types of work done by system 2 metacognition</title>
<p>We can distinguish three different types of work done by system 2 metacognition. First (W1), it makes metacognitive representations available for verbal report and hence for communication. Second (W2), system 2 metacognition works out the significance of metacognitive representations that have been broadcast or selected for communication, that is, what the individual or group should do (e.g., try harder, start again, give low weighting to that person's opinion) when a metacognitive representation has a certain range of values (e.g., indicates disfluency or lack of confidence). Although system 1 processes already contain some metacognitive representations which system 2 metacognition can select to make available (‘direct access’
<xref rid="bib0195" ref-type="bibr">[39]</xref>
), a third type of work done by system 2 metacognition (W3) is to construct or infer metacognitive representations from multiple sources of (sometimes weak) metacognitive information (
<xref rid="tb0005" ref-type="boxed-text">Box 1</xref>
,
<xref rid="fig0010" ref-type="fig">Figure 2</xref>
).</p>
<p>In addition, we can, as mentioned above, distinguish between synchronic and diachronic supra-personal cognitive control. In cases of synchronic coordinated agency, metacognitive representations are used to improve the performance of two or more people when working on the same task at the same time. Metacognitive representations can also be used diachronically in teaching other agents how to think and act in the future, to improve subsequent performance in coordinated action
<xref rid="bib0200" ref-type="bibr">[40]</xref>
, and possibly also in solitary tasks
<xref rid="bib0205" ref-type="bibr">[41]</xref>
. The interpretation of metacognitive representations, and what to do about them, can be altered through discussion with others, enabling the generation of cultural consensus and regulation concerning what the cues mean and why some instructions are more appropriate than others. For example, using system 2 metacognition, groups develop and pass on theories about system 1 processes (about how to think)
<xref rid="bib0185" ref-type="bibr">[37]</xref>
. Learnt reliance on shared metacognitive representations can be effective even though people can be very unreliable in reporting some of the object level information used by system 1 processes. For example, people are wildly incorrect about the object level information used by the system 1 processes involved in catching a ball, but can still share metacognitive information to facilitate joint performance
<xref rid="bib0175 bib0210" ref-type="bibr">[35,42]</xref>
.</p>
<p>When is system 2 metacognition direct and when is it inferred (W3)? We suppose that direct access will be used where the information is available, for example, confidence in perceptual decision making; and inferred otherwise, for example, in predictive ease of learning judgements
<xref rid="bib0045 bib0215" ref-type="bibr">[9,43]</xref>
(
<xref rid="tb0005" ref-type="boxed-text">Box 1</xref>
). If direct, there should be a reasonably tight correlation between the subject's reports (e.g., of accuracy) and objective measures
<xref rid="bib0220 bib0225" ref-type="bibr">[44,45]</xref>
. If system 2 has to infer the metacognitive significance of system 1 cues there is more room for error.</p>
</sec>
<sec id="sec0040">
<title>Examples and limitations of system 2 metacognition</title>
<p>One central source of metacognitive representations is the prediction errors generated and used by many system 1 processes to guide learning
<xref rid="bib0230" ref-type="bibr">[46]</xref>
. When relied on to guide learning and behaviour prediction errors can represent the reliability of another of the system's representations (e.g., of the value of an option) and lead that representation to be revised for the future
<xref rid="bib0235" ref-type="bibr">[47]</xref>
. Large prediction errors may produce feelings of perceptual disfluency
<xref rid="bib0240" ref-type="bibr">[48]</xref>
or action selection disfluency
<xref rid="bib0245" ref-type="bibr">[49]</xref>
. System 2 can learn the significance of these feelings and use them for cognitive control.</p>
<p>System 2 has limited processing capacity, thus it can only make use of a limited number of metacognitive representations. That number should decrease as other demands on general working memory increase. And indeed there is some evidence that under cognitive load subjects switch from relying on several raw cues to depending on a single summary
<xref rid="bib0250" ref-type="bibr">[50]</xref>
. An example of such a summary is the z-score (derived from the mean and the standard deviation of the internal perceptual representation) communicated by subjects in social psychophysics experiments
<xref rid="bib0160" ref-type="bibr">[32]</xref>
, although it is not known whether subjects could have communicated the raw cues independently. In some cases, the raw cues on which summaries are based may no longer be available. However, this mandatory fusion occurs relatively late in development (∼12 years
<xref rid="bib0255" ref-type="bibr">[51]</xref>
), suggesting that adults could learn to unpack the summary if necessary.</p>
</sec>
</sec>
<sec id="sec0045">
<title>The function of system 2 metacognition</title>
<sec id="sec0050">
<title>The functional claim about system 2 metacognition comes in various strengths</title>
<p>We have suggested that system 2 metacognition is for supra-personal cognitive control. The functional claim – what system 2 metacognition is ‘for’ – comes in several strengths. A modest claim is that system 2 metacognition is functionally involved in cases of inter-agent cognitive control; in situations where two or more people successfully coordinate their actions to achieve an outcome that depends on sensorimotor processes found in both. A bolder hypothesis is that this is the evolutionary purpose of system 2 metacognition: that the ability to represent metacognitive information in system 2 evolved to allow people to engage in more sophisticated cooperative projects and coordination tasks.</p>
</sec>
<sec id="sec0055">
<title>The hypothesis that system 2 metacognition evolved for supra-personal cognitive control</title>
<p>There is not scope here to properly assess the evolutionary claim, but we will note an empirical consequence. Humans are a distinctively cooperative mammal, engaging in coordinated behaviour to an extent that is markedly different from even our closest primate cousins
<xref rid="bib0260 bib0265" ref-type="bibr">[52,53]</xref>
. If the ability to use system 2 to select, construct, and broadcast metacognitive representations arose in humans in response to selection pressure for increasingly complex forms of coordinated action, then in non-human animals we would not expect to find a system 2 that processes metacognitive representations (
<xref rid="tb0010" ref-type="boxed-text">Box 2</xref>
). One possibility is that non-human animals do not have a system 2 at all. Alternatively, non-human animals may have system 2 functions, such as maintenance in working memory and selective attention
<xref rid="bib0270 bib0275" ref-type="bibr">[54,55]</xref>
, that do not involve the use of metacognitive information. In this case, what evolved in the hominin line was the capacity to take metacognitive representations in system 1 and turn them into metacognitive representations for system 2.</p>
<p>According to this evolutionary hypothesis, supra-personal coordination was the origin of system 2 metacognition. Using conscious metacognitive representations to control one's own individual behaviour is probably the most obvious manifestation of system 2 metacognition in everyday life. But on our account, using metacognitive representations about one's own cognitive processes for intra-personal cognitive control came second, and arose as a side effect of the selection of system 2 metacognition for inter-personally coordinated action. The picture is of cooperation becoming a central feature of the human way of life, in the form of fluidly coordinated joint action and diachronically organised cooperative projects, both controlled by a supra-personal system of cognitive control. This system directs resources and activity between a variety of different sensorimotor processes that are distributed across agents. It relies on selected metacognitive representations which, because they are shared among the agents involved, enable more efficient and complex forms of coordinated action. The selection and sharing occurs not only synchronically, while a particular episode of coordinated action is in progress, but also diachronically, as system 2 metacognition allows experts to teach novices how to use metacognitive representations in future episodes of coordinated and solitary tasks.</p>
<p>The selection processes favouring the emergence of system 2 metacognition could have been genetic and/or cultural. To the extent that the evolutionary processes were genetic, rather than cultural, one would expect: (i) little cross-cultural variation in the extent and content of system 2 metacognition, especially when people are tested in coordinated action tasks and when adults are teaching children; and (ii) that metacognitive competence would emerge early and independently of instruction. If these predictions are false
<xref rid="bib0280" ref-type="bibr">[56]</xref>
, it would suggest a role for cultural selection in the evolution of system 2 metacognition (see section on ‘Empirical predictions’ below).</p>
</sec>
<sec id="sec0060">
<title>An (even) more radical evolutionary hypothesis about system 2 metacognition</title>
<p>The evolutionary claim about the function of system 2 metacognition in turn comes in various strengths. So far, we have suggested that it was the ability to represent metacognitive information in system 2 that was selected. This allows that early hominins may already have had system 2 in place, and perhaps also natural language (which may or may not be separable from the presence of system 2). However, it is worth noting that a much more radical evolutionary claim could also be entertained: that system 2 itself evolved to perform the function of selecting, constructing, and broadcasting metacognitive representations in the service of supra-personal cognitive control. A yet further evolutionary question on which we do not venture to speculate is the relation of these various evolutionary steps to the emergence of consciousness.</p>
</sec>
</sec>
<sec id="sec0065">
<title>Empirical predictions</title>
<p>We suggest several empirical predictions against which our hypothesis can be tested. The first concerns linguistic communication. It follows from our functional hypothesis that some forms of joint action are significantly aided by communication of metacognitive representations selected by system 2 metacognition. Thus, in a novel task requiring two or more agents to act jointly in pursuit of some goal (i.e., not one where an action plan has been automatised in system 1 processes in both agents), blocking the linguistic communication of metacognitive information should have a selective detrimental effect on performance, in a way that blocking the linguistic communication of object level information about the task does not.</p>
<p>Similarly, in such a novel coordination task, cognitive load should selectively impair performance, and should do so via an effect on the (accuracy or range) of communicated metacognitive information. By contrast, where automatic/autonomous/implicit processes rely on metacognitive information in directing behaviour or resources between sensorimotor processes, increased cognitive load should cause relatively little impairment.</p>
<p>A third prediction concerns individual differences. Performance in the types of novel coordination tasks just described should correlate with individual differences in measures of general intelligence.</p>
<p>Our final prediction concerns non-human animals. If, contrary to our hypothesis, non-human animals have system 2 metacognition, they should be able to learn that reward-seeking behaviour is successful after making decisions that are unlikely to be correct (low confidence) and unsuccessful after making decisions that are likely to be correct (high confidence). This could be tested by, for example, using a reverse transfer test after training in a wagering task.</p>
</sec>
<sec id="sec0070">
<title>Concluding remarks</title>
<p>As yet the evidence for our hypothesis is limited and there are many outstanding questions (
<xref rid="tb0015" ref-type="boxed-text">Box 3</xref>
). The two key components, for which there is some preliminary evidence, are: (i) that system 2 metacognition is very malleable and readily influenced by instructions and beliefs
<xref rid="bib0280 bib0285" ref-type="bibr">[56,57]</xref>
; and (ii) that exchange of system 2 metacognitive representations can create advantages for the group
<xref rid="bib0160" ref-type="bibr">[32]</xref>
. If tests of our empirical predictions provide further support, it would suggest that metacognition is a specific form of cognitive control and is not unique to system 2. Metacognitive information such as decision uncertainty is used to modulate ongoing thought and behaviour in the absence of awareness. These implicit metacognitive representations enable the many different processes that make up system 1 to work together in an optimal manner. However, when metacognitive representations are explicit in system 2 they can be readily used to enable several people to work together in an optimal manner, for example, by sharing information about decision confidence. We suggest that explicit metacognitive representations exist for this reason. This role is possible, first because the representations are in verbal form suitable for sharing, and second because they can modify the functioning of system 1. On the basis of metacognitive signals emerging from system 1, accounts are developed in system 2 designed to explain and control the functioning of system 1. These accounts can be sketchy and inaccurate, like any narrative, but are constantly updated and sometimes improved through discussion with others. This process provides a mechanism for modification of behaviour through instructions and cultural expectations. These are powerful forces that alter behaviour of whole groups of people and provide a mechanism for the emergence of cumulative culture.</p>
</sec>
</body>
<back>
<ref-list>
<title>References</title>
<ref id="bib0005">
<label>1</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0005">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Block</surname>
<given-names>N.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Two neural correlates of consciousness</article-title>
<source>Trends Cogn. Sci.</source>
<volume>9</volume>
<year>2005</year>
<fpage>46</fpage>
<lpage>52</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">15668096</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0010">
<label>2</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0010">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Kahneman</surname>
<given-names>D.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>A perspective on judgment and choice: mapping bounded rationality</article-title>
<source>Am. Psychol.</source>
<volume>58</volume>
<year>2003</year>
<fpage>697</fpage>
<lpage>720</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">14584987</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0015">
<label>3</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0015">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Evans</surname>
<given-names>J.S.B.T.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Stanovich</surname>
<given-names>K.E.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Dual-process theories of higher cognition advancing the debate</article-title>
<source>Perspect. Psychol. Sci.</source>
<volume>8</volume>
<year>2013</year>
<fpage>223</fpage>
<lpage>241</lpage>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0020">
<label>4</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0020">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Kiani</surname>
<given-names>R.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Shadlen</surname>
<given-names>M.N.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Representation of confidence associated with a decision by neurons in the parietal cortex</article-title>
<source>Science</source>
<volume>324</volume>
<year>2009</year>
<fpage>759</fpage>
<lpage>764</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">19423820</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0025">
<label>5</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0025">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Kepecs</surname>
<given-names>A.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Neural correlates, computation and behavioural impact of decision confidence</article-title>
<source>Nature</source>
<volume>455</volume>
<year>2008</year>
<fpage>227</fpage>
<lpage>231</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">18690210</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0030">
<label>6</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0030">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Komura</surname>
<given-names>Y.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Responses of pulvinar neurons reflect a subject's confidence in visual categorization</article-title>
<source>Nat. Neurosci.</source>
<volume>16</volume>
<year>2013</year>
<fpage>749</fpage>
<lpage>755</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">23666179</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0035">
<label>7</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0035">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Terrace</surname>
<given-names>H.S.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Son</surname>
<given-names>L.K.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Comparative metacognition</article-title>
<source>Curr. Opin. Neurobiol.</source>
<volume>19</volume>
<year>2009</year>
<fpage>67</fpage>
<lpage>74</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">19553102</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0040">
<label>8</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0040">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Carruthers</surname>
<given-names>P.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>How we know our own minds: the relationship between mindreading and metacognition</article-title>
<source>Behav. Brain Sci.</source>
<volume>32</volume>
<year>2009</year>
<fpage>121</fpage>
<lpage>182</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">19386144</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0045">
<label>9</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0045">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Metcalfe</surname>
<given-names>J.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Metacognitive judgments and control of study</article-title>
<source>Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci.</source>
<volume>18</volume>
<year>2009</year>
<fpage>159</fpage>
<lpage>163</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">19750138</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0050">
<label>10</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0050">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Fernandez-Duque</surname>
<given-names>D.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Executive attention and metacognitive regulation</article-title>
<source>Conscious. Cogn.</source>
<volume>9</volume>
<year>2000</year>
<fpage>288</fpage>
<lpage>307</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">10924249</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0055">
<label>11</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0055">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Drugowitsch</surname>
<given-names>J.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Pouget</surname>
<given-names>A.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Probabilistic vs. non-probabilistic approaches to the neurobiology of perceptual decision-making</article-title>
<source>Curr. Opin. Neurobiol.</source>
<volume>22</volume>
<year>2012</year>
<fpage>963</fpage>
<lpage>969</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">22884815</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0060">
<label>12</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0060">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Ernst</surname>
<given-names>M.O.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Banks</surname>
<given-names>M.S.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Humans integrate visual and haptic information in a statistically optimal fashion</article-title>
<source>Nature</source>
<volume>415</volume>
<year>2002</year>
<fpage>429</fpage>
<lpage>433</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">11807554</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0065">
<label>13</label>
<element-citation publication-type="book" id="sbref0065">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Davelaar</surname>
<given-names>E.J.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<chapter-title>Conflict-monitoring and (meta)cognitive control</chapter-title>
<person-group person-group-type="editor">
<name>
<surname>Mayor</surname>
<given-names>J.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<source>Connectionist Models of Behaviour and Cognition II. Proceedings of the 11th Neural Computation and Psychology Worksho</source>
<year>2009</year>
<publisher-name>WorldScientific</publisher-name>
<fpage>91</fpage>
<lpage>102</lpage>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0070">
<label>14</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0070">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Davis</surname>
<given-names>E.L.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Metacognitive emotion regulation: children's awareness that changing thoughts and goals can alleviate negative emotions</article-title>
<source>Emotion</source>
<volume>10</volume>
<year>2010</year>
<fpage>498</fpage>
<lpage>510</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">20677867</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0075">
<label>15</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0075">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Shenhav</surname>
<given-names>A.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>The expected value of control: an integrative theory of anterior cingulate cortex function</article-title>
<source>Neuron</source>
<volume>79</volume>
<year>2013</year>
<fpage>217</fpage>
<lpage>240</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">23889930</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0080">
<label>16</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0080">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Sakai</surname>
<given-names>K.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Task set and prefrontal cortex</article-title>
<source>Annu. Rev. Neurosci.</source>
<volume>31</volume>
<year>2008</year>
<fpage>219</fpage>
<lpage>245</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">18558854</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0085">
<label>17</label>
<element-citation publication-type="book" id="sbref0085">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Yeung</surname>
<given-names>N.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<chapter-title>Conflict monitoring and cognitive control</chapter-title>
<person-group person-group-type="editor">
<name>
<surname>Ochsner</surname>
<given-names>K.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Kosslyn</surname>
<given-names>S.M.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<series>Oxford Handbook of Cognitive Neuroscience</series>
<volume>Vol. 2</volume>
<year>2013</year>
<publisher-name>Oxford University Press</publisher-name>
<fpage>275</fpage>
<lpage>299</lpage>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0090">
<label>18</label>
<element-citation publication-type="book" id="sbref0090">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Norman</surname>
<given-names>D.A.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Shallice</surname>
<given-names>T.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<chapter-title>Attention to action: willed and automatic control of behaviour</chapter-title>
<person-group person-group-type="editor">
<name>
<surname>Davidson</surname>
<given-names>R.J.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<source>Consciousness and Self-regulation (Advances in Research and Theory, Vol. 4)</source>
<year>1986</year>
<publisher-name>Plenum</publisher-name>
<fpage>1</fpage>
<lpage>18</lpage>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0095">
<label>19</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0095">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Desimone</surname>
<given-names>R.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Duncan</surname>
<given-names>J.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Neural mechanisms of selective visual attention</article-title>
<source>Annu. Rev. Neurosci.</source>
<volume>18</volume>
<year>1995</year>
<fpage>193</fpage>
<lpage>222</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">7605061</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0100">
<label>20</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0100">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Dehaene</surname>
<given-names>S.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Naccache</surname>
<given-names>L.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Towards a cognitive neuroscience of consciousness: basic evidence and a workspace framework</article-title>
<source>Cognition</source>
<volume>79</volume>
<year>2001</year>
<fpage>1</fpage>
<lpage>37</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">11164022</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0105">
<label>21</label>
<element-citation publication-type="book" id="sbref0105">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Kahneman</surname>
<given-names>D.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<chapter-title>Thinking Fast and Slow</chapter-title>
<year>2011</year>
<publisher-name>Macmillan</publisher-name>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0110">
<label>22</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0110">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Sumner</surname>
<given-names>P.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Human medial frontal cortex mediates unconscious inhibition of voluntary action</article-title>
<source>Neuron</source>
<volume>54</volume>
<year>2007</year>
<fpage>697</fpage>
<lpage>711</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">17553420</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0115">
<label>23</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0115">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Custers</surname>
<given-names>R.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Aarts</surname>
<given-names>H.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>The unconscious will: how the pursuit of goals operates outside of conscious awareness</article-title>
<source>Science</source>
<volume>329</volume>
<year>2010</year>
<fpage>47</fpage>
<lpage>50</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">20595607</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0120">
<label>24</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0120">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Logan</surname>
<given-names>G.D.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Crump</surname>
<given-names>M.J.C.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Cognitive illusions of authorship reveal hierarchical error detection in skilled typists</article-title>
<source>Science</source>
<volume>330</volume>
<year>2010</year>
<fpage>683</fpage>
<lpage>686</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">21030660</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0125">
<label>25</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0125">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Naccache</surname>
<given-names>L.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Effortless control: executive attention and conscious feeling of mental effort are dissociable</article-title>
<source>Neuropsychologia</source>
<volume>43</volume>
<year>2005</year>
<fpage>1318</fpage>
<lpage>1328</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">15949516</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0130">
<label>26</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0130">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Bach</surname>
<given-names>D.R.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Dolan</surname>
<given-names>R.J.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Knowing how much you don’t know: a neural organization of uncertainty estimates</article-title>
<source>Nat. Rev. Neurosci.</source>
<volume>13</volume>
<year>2012</year>
<fpage>572</fpage>
<lpage>586</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">22781958</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0135">
<label>27</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0135">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Summerfield</surname>
<given-names>C.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Yeung</surname>
<given-names>N.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Oh, rats! Post-error behavioral adjustment in creatures great and small</article-title>
<source>Nat. Neurosci.</source>
<volume>16</volume>
<year>2013</year>
<fpage>1715</fpage>
<lpage>1716</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">24270271</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0140">
<label>28</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0140">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Richardson</surname>
<given-names>M.J.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Rocking together: dynamics of intentional and unintentional interpersonal coordination</article-title>
<source>Hum. Mov. Sci.</source>
<volume>26</volume>
<year>2007</year>
<fpage>867</fpage>
<lpage>891</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">17765345</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0145">
<label>29</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0145">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Hasson</surname>
<given-names>U.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Brain-to-brain coupling: a mechanism for creating and sharing a social world</article-title>
<source>Trends Cogn. Sci.</source>
<volume>16</volume>
<year>2012</year>
<fpage>114</fpage>
<lpage>121</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">22221820</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0150">
<label>30</label>
<element-citation publication-type="book" id="sbref0150">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Byrne</surname>
<given-names>R.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Whiten</surname>
<given-names>A.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<chapter-title>Machiavellian Intelligence: Social Expertise and the Evolution of Intellect in Monkeys, Apes and Humans</chapter-title>
<year>1989</year>
<publisher-name>Oxford Science Publications</publisher-name>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0155">
<label>31</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0155">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Herrmann</surname>
<given-names>E.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Humans have evolved specialized skills of social cognition: the cultural intelligence hypothesis</article-title>
<source>Science</source>
<volume>317</volume>
<year>2007</year>
<fpage>1360</fpage>
<lpage>1366</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">17823346</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0160">
<label>32</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0160">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Bahrami</surname>
<given-names>B.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Optimally interacting minds</article-title>
<source>Science</source>
<volume>329</volume>
<year>2010</year>
<fpage>1081</fpage>
<lpage>1085</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">20798320</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0165">
<label>33</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0165">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Fusaroli</surname>
<given-names>R.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Coming to terms quantifying the benefits of linguistic coordination</article-title>
<source>Psychol. Sci.</source>
<volume>23</volume>
<year>2012</year>
<fpage>931</fpage>
<lpage>939</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">22810169</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0170">
<label>34</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0170">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Tenney</surname>
<given-names>E.R.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Calibration trumps confidence as a basis for witness credibility</article-title>
<source>Psychol. Sci.</source>
<volume>18</volume>
<year>2007</year>
<fpage>46</fpage>
<lpage>50</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">17362377</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0175">
<label>35</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0175">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Poizat</surname>
<given-names>G.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Analysis of contextual information sharing during table tennis matches: an empirical study of coordination in sports</article-title>
<source>Int. J. Sport Exerc. Psychol.</source>
<volume>7</volume>
<year>2009</year>
<fpage>465</fpage>
<lpage>487</lpage>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0180">
<label>36</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0180">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Lausic</surname>
<given-names>D.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Intrateam communication and performance in doubles tennis</article-title>
<source>Res. Q. Exerc. Sport</source>
<volume>80</volume>
<year>2009</year>
<fpage>281</fpage>
<lpage>290</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">19650394</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0185">
<label>37</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0185">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Job</surname>
<given-names>V.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Ego depletion – Is it all in your head? Implicit theories about willpower affect self-regulation</article-title>
<source>Psychol. Sci.</source>
<volume>21</volume>
<year>2010</year>
<fpage>1686</fpage>
<lpage>1693</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">20876879</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0190">
<label>38</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0190">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Hurks</surname>
<given-names>P.P.M.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Does instruction in semantic clustering and switching enhance verbal fluency in children?</article-title>
<source>Clin. Neuropsychol.</source>
<volume>26</volume>
<year>2012</year>
<fpage>1019</fpage>
<lpage>1037</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">22823962</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0195">
<label>39</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0195">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Koriat</surname>
<given-names>A.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>The self-consistency model of subjective confidence</article-title>
<source>Psychol. Rev.</source>
<volume>119</volume>
<year>2012</year>
<fpage>80</fpage>
<lpage>113</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">22022833</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0200">
<label>40</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0200">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Bahrami</surname>
<given-names>B.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Together, slowly but surely: the role of social interaction and feedback on the build-up of benefit in collective decision-making</article-title>
<source>J. Exp. Psychol. Hum. Percept. Perform.</source>
<volume>38</volume>
<year>2012</year>
<fpage>3</fpage>
<lpage>8</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">21988362</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0205">
<label>41</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0205">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Payne</surname>
<given-names>B.D.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Manning</surname>
<given-names>B.H.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Basal reader instruction: effects of comprehension monitoring training on reading comprehension, strategy use and attitude</article-title>
<source>Read. Res. Instr.</source>
<volume>32</volume>
<year>1992</year>
<fpage>29</fpage>
<lpage>38</lpage>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0210">
<label>42</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0210">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Reed</surname>
<given-names>N.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Implicit knowledge and motor skill: what people who know how to catch don’t know</article-title>
<source>Conscious. Cogn.</source>
<volume>19</volume>
<year>2010</year>
<fpage>63</fpage>
<lpage>76</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">19703779</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0215">
<label>43</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0215">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Meiser</surname>
<given-names>T.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Metacognitive inferences in source memory judgements: the role of perceived differences in item recognition</article-title>
<source>Q. J. Exp. Psychol.</source>
<volume>60</volume>
<year>2007</year>
<fpage>1015</fpage>
<lpage>1040</lpage>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0220">
<label>44</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0220">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Brewer</surname>
<given-names>W.F.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Sampaio</surname>
<given-names>C.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>The metamemory approach to confidence: a test using semantic memory</article-title>
<source>J. Mem. Lang.</source>
<volume>67</volume>
<year>2012</year>
<fpage>59</fpage>
<lpage>77</lpage>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0225">
<label>45</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0225">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Overgaard</surname>
<given-names>M.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Sandberg</surname>
<given-names>K.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Kinds of access: different methods for report reveal different kinds of metacognitive access</article-title>
<source>Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B: Biol. Sci.</source>
<volume>367</volume>
<year>2012</year>
<fpage>1287</fpage>
<lpage>1296</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">22492747</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0230">
<label>46</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0230">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Friston</surname>
<given-names>K.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>The free-energy principle: a unified brain theory?</article-title>
<source>Nat. Rev. Neurosci.</source>
<volume>11</volume>
<year>2010</year>
<fpage>127</fpage>
<lpage>138</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">20068583</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0235">
<label>47</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0235">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Shea</surname>
<given-names>N.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Reward prediction error signals are meta-representational</article-title>
<source>Nous</source>
<year>2012</year>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0240">
<label>48</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0240">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Yue</surname>
<given-names>C.L.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>When disfluency is – and is not – a desirable difficulty: the influence of typeface clarity on metacognitive judgments and memory</article-title>
<source>Mem. Cogn.</source>
<volume>41</volume>
<year>2013</year>
<fpage>229</fpage>
<lpage>241</lpage>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0245">
<label>49</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0245">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Chambon</surname>
<given-names>V.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Haggard</surname>
<given-names>P.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Sense of control depends on fluency of action selection, not motor performance</article-title>
<source>Cognition</source>
<volume>125</volume>
<year>2012</year>
<fpage>441</fpage>
<lpage>451</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">22902284</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0250">
<label>50</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0250">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Hoffman</surname>
<given-names>Y.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Explicit memory for unattended words the importance of being in the ‘no’</article-title>
<source>Psychol. Sci.</source>
<volume>22</volume>
<year>2011</year>
<fpage>1490</fpage>
<lpage>1493</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">22115962</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0255">
<label>51</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0255">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Nardini</surname>
<given-names>M.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Fusion of visual cues is not mandatory in children</article-title>
<source>Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A.</source>
<volume>107</volume>
<year>2010</year>
<fpage>17041</fpage>
<lpage>17046</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">20837526</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0260">
<label>52</label>
<element-citation publication-type="book" id="sbref0260">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Tomasello</surname>
<given-names>M.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<chapter-title>Why We Cooperate</chapter-title>
<year>2009</year>
<publisher-name>MIT Press</publisher-name>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0265">
<label>53</label>
<element-citation publication-type="book" id="sbref0265">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Sterelny</surname>
<given-names>K.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<chapter-title>The Evolved Apprentice</chapter-title>
<year>2012</year>
<publisher-name>MIT Press</publisher-name>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0270">
<label>54</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0270">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Matzel</surname>
<given-names>L.D.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Kolata</surname>
<given-names>S.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Selective attention, working memory, and animal intelligence</article-title>
<source>Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev.</source>
<volume>34</volume>
<year>2010</year>
<fpage>23</fpage>
<lpage>30</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">19607858</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0275">
<label>55</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0275">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Dickinson</surname>
<given-names>A.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Associative learning and animal cognition</article-title>
<source>Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B: Biol. Sci.</source>
<volume>367</volume>
<year>2012</year>
<fpage>2733</fpage>
<lpage>2742</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">22927572</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0280">
<label>56</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0280">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Mayer</surname>
<given-names>A.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Träuble</surname>
<given-names>B.E.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Synchrony in the onset of mental state understanding across cultures? A study among children in Samoa</article-title>
<source>Int. J. Behav. Dev.</source>
<volume>37</volume>
<year>2013</year>
<fpage>21</fpage>
<lpage>28</lpage>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0285">
<label>57</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0285">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Rigoni</surname>
<given-names>D.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Inducing disbelief in free will alters brain correlates of preconscious motor preparation: the brain minds whether we believe in free will or not</article-title>
<source>Psychol. Sci.</source>
<volume>22</volume>
<year>2011</year>
<fpage>613</fpage>
<lpage>618</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">21515737</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0290">
<label>58</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0290">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Pleskac</surname>
<given-names>T.J.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Busemeyer</surname>
<given-names>J.R.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Two-stage dynamic signal detection: a theory of choice, decision time, and confidence</article-title>
<source>Psychol. Rev.</source>
<volume>117</volume>
<year>2010</year>
<fpage>864</fpage>
<lpage>901</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">20658856</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0295">
<label>59</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0295">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Yeung</surname>
<given-names>N.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Summerfield</surname>
<given-names>C.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Metacognition in human decision-making: confidence and error monitoring</article-title>
<source>Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B: Biol. Sci.</source>
<volume>367</volume>
<year>2012</year>
<fpage>1310</fpage>
<lpage>1321</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">22492749</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0300">
<label>60</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0300">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Pasquali</surname>
<given-names>A.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Know thyself: metacognitive networks and measures of consciousness</article-title>
<source>Cognition</source>
<volume>117</volume>
<year>2010</year>
<fpage>182</fpage>
<lpage>190</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">20825936</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0305">
<label>61</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0305">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Smith</surname>
<given-names>J.D.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>The highs and lows of theoretical interpretation in animal-metacognition research</article-title>
<source>Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B: Biol. Sci.</source>
<volume>367</volume>
<year>2012</year>
<fpage>1297</fpage>
<lpage>1309</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">22492748</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0310">
<label>62</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0310">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Schwartz</surname>
<given-names>B.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Sources of information in metamemory: judgments of learning and feelings of knowing</article-title>
<source>Psychon. Bull. Rev.</source>
<volume>1</volume>
<year>1994</year>
<fpage>357</fpage>
<lpage>375</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">24203520</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0315">
<label>63</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0315">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Gigerenzer</surname>
<given-names>G.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Probabilistic mental models: a Brunswikian theory of confidence</article-title>
<source>Psychol. Rev.</source>
<volume>98</volume>
<year>1991</year>
<fpage>506</fpage>
<lpage>528</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">1961771</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0320">
<label>64</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0320">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Higham</surname>
<given-names>P.A.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Investigating strength and frequency effects in recognition memory using type-2 signal detection theory</article-title>
<source>J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Mem. Cogn.</source>
<volume>35</volume>
<year>2009</year>
<fpage>57</fpage>
<lpage>80</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">19210081</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0325">
<label>65</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0325">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Peirce</surname>
<given-names>C.S.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Illustrations of the logic of science: the probability of induction</article-title>
<source>Popular Sci. Monthly</source>
<volume>12</volume>
<year>1877</year>
<fpage>705</fpage>
<lpage>718</lpage>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0330">
<label>66</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0330">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Charles</surname>
<given-names>L.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Distinct brain mechanisms for conscious versus subliminal error detection</article-title>
<source>Neuroimage</source>
<volume>73</volume>
<year>2013</year>
<fpage>80</fpage>
<lpage>94</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">23380166</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0335">
<label>67</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0335">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Middlebrooks</surname>
<given-names>P.G.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Sommer</surname>
<given-names>M.A.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Neuronal correlates of metacognition in primate frontal cortex</article-title>
<source>Neuron</source>
<volume>75</volume>
<year>2012</year>
<fpage>517</fpage>
<lpage>530</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">22884334</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0340">
<label>68</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0340">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Kepecs</surname>
<given-names>A.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Mainen</surname>
<given-names>Z.F.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>A computational framework for the study of confidence in humans and animals</article-title>
<source>Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B: Biol. Sci.</source>
<volume>367</volume>
<year>2012</year>
<fpage>1322</fpage>
<lpage>1337</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">22492750</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0345">
<label>69</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0345">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Hanks</surname>
<given-names>T.D.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Elapsed decision time affects the weighting of prior probability in a perceptual decision task</article-title>
<source>J. Neurosci.</source>
<volume>31</volume>
<year>2011</year>
<fpage>6339</fpage>
<lpage>6352</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">21525274</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0350">
<label>70</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0350">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Moreno-Bote</surname>
<given-names>R.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Decision confidence and uncertainty in diffusion models with partially correlated neuronal integrators</article-title>
<source>Neural Comput.</source>
<volume>22</volume>
<year>2010</year>
<fpage>1786</fpage>
<lpage>1811</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">20141474</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0355">
<label>71</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0355">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Zylberberg</surname>
<given-names>A.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>The construction of confidence in a perceptual decision</article-title>
<source>Front. Integr. Neurosci.</source>
<volume>6</volume>
<year>2012</year>
<fpage>79</fpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">23049504</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0360">
<label>72</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0360">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Koriat</surname>
<given-names>A.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>How do we know that we know? The accessibility model of the feeling of knowing</article-title>
<source>Psychol. Rev.</source>
<volume>100</volume>
<year>1993</year>
<fpage>609</fpage>
<lpage>639</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">8255951</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0365">
<label>73</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0365">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Castel</surname>
<given-names>A.D.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Illusions of competence and overestimation of associative memory for identical items: evidence from judgments of learning</article-title>
<source>Psychon. Bull. Rev.</source>
<volume>14</volume>
<year>2007</year>
<fpage>107</fpage>
<lpage>111</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">17546739</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0370">
<label>74</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0370">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Hertzog</surname>
<given-names>C.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Episodic feeling-of-knowing resolution derives from the quality of original encoding</article-title>
<source>Mem. Cogn.</source>
<volume>38</volume>
<year>2010</year>
<fpage>771</fpage>
<lpage>784</lpage>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0375">
<label>75</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0375">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Koriat</surname>
<given-names>A.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Subjective confidence in perceptual judgments: a test of the self-consistency model</article-title>
<source>J. Exp. Psychol. Gen.</source>
<volume>140</volume>
<year>2011</year>
<fpage>117</fpage>
<lpage>139</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">21299320</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0380">
<label>76</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0380">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Call</surname>
<given-names>J.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Do apes know that they could be wrong?</article-title>
<source>Anim. Cogn.</source>
<volume>13</volume>
<year>2010</year>
<fpage>689</fpage>
<lpage>700</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">20306102</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0385">
<label>77</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0385">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Beran</surname>
<given-names>M.J.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Smith</surname>
<given-names>J.D.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Information seeking by rhesus monkeys (
<italic>Macaca mulatta</italic>
) and capuchin monkeys (
<italic>Cebus apella</italic>
)</article-title>
<source>Cognition</source>
<volume>120</volume>
<year>2010</year>
<fpage>90</fpage>
<lpage>105</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">21459372</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0390">
<label>78</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0390">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Foote</surname>
<given-names>A.L.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Crystal</surname>
<given-names>J.D.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Metacognition in the rat</article-title>
<source>Curr. Biol.</source>
<volume>17</volume>
<year>2007</year>
<fpage>551</fpage>
<lpage>555</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">17346969</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0395">
<label>79</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0395">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Adams</surname>
<given-names>A.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Santi</surname>
<given-names>A.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Pigeons exhibit higher accuracy for chosen memory tests than for forced memory tests in duration matching-to-sample</article-title>
<source>Learn. Behav.</source>
<volume>39</volume>
<year>2011</year>
<fpage>1</fpage>
<lpage>11</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">21264568</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0400">
<label>80</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0400">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Templer</surname>
<given-names>V.L.</given-names>
</name>
<name>
<surname>Hampton</surname>
<given-names>R.R.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Rhesus monkeys (
<italic>Macaca mulatta</italic>
) show robust evidence for memory awareness across multiple generalization tests</article-title>
<source>Anim. Cogn.</source>
<volume>15</volume>
<year>2012</year>
<fpage>409</fpage>
<lpage>419</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">22183204</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0405">
<label>81</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0405">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Kornell</surname>
<given-names>N.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Transfer of metacognitive skills and hint seeking in monkeys</article-title>
<source>Psychol. Sci.</source>
<volume>18</volume>
<year>2007</year>
<fpage>64</fpage>
<lpage>71</lpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">17362380</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
<ref id="bib0410">
<label>82</label>
<element-citation publication-type="journal" id="sbref0410">
<person-group person-group-type="author">
<name>
<surname>Le Pelley</surname>
<given-names>M.E.</given-names>
</name>
</person-group>
<article-title>Metacognitive monkeys or associative animals? Simple reinforcement learning explains uncertainty in nonhuman animals</article-title>
<source>J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Mem. Cogn.</source>
<volume>38</volume>
<year>2012</year>
<fpage>686</fpage>
<pub-id pub-id-type="pmid">22250905</pub-id>
</element-citation>
</ref>
</ref-list>
<glossary id="glo0005">
<title>Glossary</title>
<def-list>
<def-item>
<term>Cognitive control</term>
<def>
<p>cognitive mechanisms responsible for guiding thought and behaviour in accordance with current goals and intentions.</p>
</def>
</def-item>
<def-item>
<term>Conscious</term>
<def>
<p>here we use the term in the sense of access consciousness [1]. A representation is access conscious just in case it can be used, without further processing, for verbal report, inferential reasoning, storage in episodic and semantic memory, and by other ‘consuming’ systems.</p>
</def>
</def-item>
<def-item>
<term>Metacognition</term>
<def>
<p>use of metacognitive representations (often, but not exclusively, for purposes of cognitive control).</p>
</def>
</def-item>
<def-item>
<term>Metacognitive information</term>
<def>
<p>information about a property of a cognitive process, for example, the variance in the firing rate of a population of neurons in visual cortex. Information is just a matter of correlation, strong or weak, and need not be used or represented.</p>
</def>
</def-item>
<def-item>
<term>Metacognitive representation</term>
<def>
<p>a representation of a property of a cognitive process, for example, the reliability of a perceptual representation. Metacognitive information that is represented and used for cognitive control is thereby a metacognitive representation, for example, the variance in the firing rate of a population of neurons in visual cortex can form the basis of a representation of the probability that the perceptual representation is correct (cf. object level representation).</p>
</def>
</def-item>
<def-item>
<term>Object level representation</term>
<def>
<p>a representation that is not at the meta-level, that is, that does not concern cognitive processes as such. Examples include representations of the nature, location, or value of a stimulus. (Similarly, correlates of such properties, whether represented or not, carry ‘object level information’.)</p>
</def>
</def-item>
<def-item>
<term>System 1 (type 1 cognitive processes)</term>
<def>
<p>a label for a number of cognitive systems that operate autonomously and do not require working memory. A system 1 process is typically fast, automatic, associative, effortless, and non-conscious. System 1 processes tend not to cause or suffer much interference when combined with one another or the performance of other tasks [2,3].</p>
</def>
</def-item>
<def-item>
<term>System 2</term>
<def>
<p>a label for a cognitive system that relies on working memory and is typically slower, serial, rule-based, more effortful, and conscious. Because of its limited capacity, processes relying on system 2 tend to disrupt each other [2,3].</p>
</def>
</def-item>
</def-list>
</glossary>
<ack id="ack0005">
<title>Acknowledgements</title>
<p>We are grateful to All Souls College for hosting and funding the series of seminars on metacognition from which our ideas have emerged. We are also grateful to all the speakers and participants of the seminars, but should make clear the ideas we present are not intended to represent any consensus of these participants. This work was supported by All Souls College, University of Oxford; the Economic and Social Research Council (A.B.); the Calleva Research Centre for Evolution and Human Sciences (D.B.); and the Wellcome Trust (CDF).</p>
</ack>
</back>
<floats-group>
<fig id="fig0005">
<label>Figure 1</label>
<caption>
<p>System 1 metacognition with a single agent. The control of cognitive processes in an individual's system 1 occurs automatically and at a sub-personal level
<xref rid="bib0015" ref-type="bibr">[3]</xref>
. Contention scheduling, a term introduced by Norman and Shallice
<xref rid="bib0090" ref-type="bibr">[18]</xref>
, refers to a mechanism for resolving competition between processes that overlap in their effector system requirements. Metacognitive representations reflect the properties of the functioning of these cognitive processes. System 1 uses metacognitive representations to improve control. An example of such representations would be the reliability of sensory signals. Cognitive processes estimated to be more reliable can be given greater weight
<xref rid="bib0060" ref-type="bibr">[12]</xref>
.</p>
</caption>
<graphic xlink:href="gr1"></graphic>
</fig>
<fig id="fig0010">
<label>Figure 2</label>
<caption>
<p>System 2 metacognition for cognitive control across two agents. System 2 metacognitive representations are derived from information in system 1, but they are in a form available for verbal report. For example, the reliability of a sensory signal can be reported in terms of confidence. When agents are cooperating, these reports can be used to optimise control by, for example, giving more weight to the more confident observer
<xref rid="bib0160" ref-type="bibr">[32]</xref>
. Via system 2, verbal reports can also have long-term effects on the functioning of system 1
<xref rid="bib0285" ref-type="bibr">[57]</xref>
.</p>
</caption>
<graphic xlink:href="gr2"></graphic>
</fig>
<boxed-text id="tb0005">
<label>Box 1</label>
<caption>
<title>Metacognition in humans</title>
</caption>
<p>Metacognition can be assessed with a range of different paradigms. Perceived (in)correctness of a first-order decision is often measured retrospectively through explicit second-order confidence or error detection judgements
<xref rid="bib0290 bib0295" ref-type="bibr">[58,59]</xref>
. Moreover, post-decision wagering requires participants to place a wager on a just made decision, assuming higher bets will follow from higher confidence
<xref rid="bib0300" ref-type="bibr">[60]</xref>
. Another measure often used in reward paradigms is opt-out or uncertainty response, which allow the participant to skip a response, obtaining a smaller but guaranteed reward
<xref rid="bib0305" ref-type="bibr">[61]</xref>
. All these judgements are diagnostic of task performance, meaning higher confidence on correct compared with error trials. This leads to the question as to what metacognitive information is being represented by system 1 and system 2 metacognition. Studies have identified a range of candidates, which can be divided into two classes: directly accessed and inferred
<xref rid="bib0195 bib0310" ref-type="bibr">[39,62]</xref>
.</p>
<p>Direct access models assume that metacognition is based on the same information as the decision itself or some property of the decision. There are cases of direct access system 1 metacognitive representations that are based on exactly the same information as the decision. For example, Gigerenzer and colleagues suggested that both decision making and confidence are based on the validity of an activated cue
<xref rid="bib0315" ref-type="bibr">[63]</xref>
. A similar assumption is made by type 2 signal detection theory
<xref rid="bib0320" ref-type="bibr">[64]</xref>
; in this class of direct access models, confidence corresponds to the quantity of decision evidence accumulated for one response option. Other properties of the decision evidence have been suggested to play a role, such as its quality. Both Peirce's model of confidence
<xref rid="bib0325" ref-type="bibr">[65]</xref>
and Kiani and Shadlen
<xref rid="bib0020" ref-type="bibr">[4]</xref>
suggest a combination of both
<xref rid="bib0290 bib0295" ref-type="bibr">[58,59]</xref>
. The idea that external variability affects confidence has also been suggested
<xref rid="bib0295" ref-type="bibr">[59]</xref>
, meaning that more variable stimuli lead to lower levels of confidence. Others have suggested cognitive conflict as a basis for metacognition
<xref rid="bib0065 bib0085" ref-type="bibr">[13,17]</xref>
, which is based on the idea of competing response tendencies. The evidence in favour of the unchosen choice option also plays a role in mismatch models, which assume that metacognition is based on an internal matching process of the intended action with the actually performed one
<xref rid="bib0330 bib0335" ref-type="bibr">[66,67]</xref>
, as well as prediction errors
<xref rid="bib0230" ref-type="bibr">[46]</xref>
. Similarly, the balance-of-evidence hypothesis is another example of direct access models, according to which, confidence is a function of the evidence for the chosen and the unchosen option
<xref rid="bib0340" ref-type="bibr">[68]</xref>
.</p>
<p>In contrast to direct access models, inferential models assume that metacognition is based on information external to the first-order decision-making process. For example, an individual may learn that information from conflicting or variable sources of evidence leads to slower responses
<xref rid="bib0345" ref-type="bibr">[69]</xref>
, and thus infer her confidence from response times, either approximated internally
<xref rid="bib0350 bib0355" ref-type="bibr">[70,71]</xref>
or through the observation of one's own or another individual's response movement. Several other inferential models, rooted in the metamemory literature, assume that metacognition is based on ease of processing, that is how accessible a representation is
<xref rid="bib0360" ref-type="bibr">[72]</xref>
, how fluently it can be processed
<xref rid="bib0365" ref-type="bibr">[73]</xref>
, or how familiar it is
<xref rid="bib0370" ref-type="bibr">[74]</xref>
. Another inferential hypothesis is the self-consistency model (SCM
<xref rid="bib0195 bib0375" ref-type="bibr">[39,75]</xref>
), based on the consensuality principle, which assumes participants have implicit knowledge of what response others would give and approximate their confidence accordingly.</p>
</boxed-text>
<boxed-text id="tb0010">
<label>Box 2</label>
<caption>
<title>Metacognition in non-human animals</title>
</caption>
<p>There is compelling evidence that non-human animals are more likely to seek additional information
<xref rid="bib0380 bib0385" ref-type="bibr">[76,77]</xref>
, to opt out of making decisions
<xref rid="bib0020 bib0025 bib0390 bib0395 bib0400" ref-type="bibr">[4,5,78–80]</xref>
, and to make lower post-decision wagers
<xref rid="bib0335 bib0405" ref-type="bibr">[67,81]</xref>
under conditions in which a human observer would describe them as uncertain; for example, when the animal is required to make a difficult rather than an easy visual discrimination, or to remember an event over a long rather than a short interval. Some recent studies of monkeys
<xref rid="bib0335" ref-type="bibr">[67]</xref>
, rats
<xref rid="bib0025 bib0390" ref-type="bibr">[5,78]</xref>
, and pigeons
<xref rid="bib0395" ref-type="bibr">[79]</xref>
have also indicated, using transfer tests and single neuron recording, that this type of metacognitive behaviour can be regulated by internal rather than external cues; for example, that it covaries more precisely with neural signals from the orbitofrontal cortex or the supplementary eye fields than with external stimulus values.</p>
<p>These data suggest that animals from a wide range of species are capable of system 1 metacognition. As we have characterised it, system 1 metacognition is undemanding (see subsection ‘Only some forms of cognitive control involve metacognition’ above). It could be mediated by simple reinforcement learning (cf.
<xref rid="bib0035 bib0410" ref-type="bibr">[7,82]</xref>
). However, the current data do not show that animals are capable of system 2 metacognition: that they are able to infer or to learn, using system 2, the metacognitive significance of system 1 cues. Even in the most compelling experiments (e.g.,
<xref rid="bib0300 bib0390" ref-type="bibr">[60,78]</xref>
), it is possible that a ‘high confidence’ internal system 1 signal, X, automatically triggered reward-seeking behaviour – and thereby reduced the probability of information-seeking, opt-out, and low post-decision wagers – without the animal having to use a system 2 process to learn that, in the presence of X, reward-seeking behaviour tends to be successful.</p>
</boxed-text>
<boxed-text id="tb0015">
<label>Box 3</label>
<caption>
<title>Outstanding questions</title>
</caption>
<p>
<list list-type="simple">
<list-item id="lsti0030">
<label></label>
<p>Is there a specific format for system 2 metacognitive representations designed to enable a common supra-personal metric (e.g., confidence as signal mean*precision)?</p>
</list-item>
<list-item id="lsti0035">
<label></label>
<p>Can cognitive control be improved through inter-personal exchange of system 2 metacognitive representations?</p>
</list-item>
<list-item id="lsti0040">
<label></label>
<p>Can the interpretation of system 2 metacognitive representations be changed/corrected through discussion (e.g., learning that perceptual fluency indicates familiarity)?</p>
</list-item>
<list-item id="lsti0045">
<label></label>
<p>What are the distinctive features of group decision making in humans in comparison to eusocial animals such as ants and bees?</p>
</list-item>
<list-item id="lsti0050">
<label></label>
<p>Are there cultural differences in the use of system 2 metacognitive representations?</p>
</list-item>
</list>
</p>
</boxed-text>
</floats-group>
</pmc>
<affiliations>
<list>
<country>
<li>Danemark</li>
<li>Royaume-Uni</li>
</country>
<region>
<li>Angleterre</li>
<li>Oxfordshire</li>
</region>
<settlement>
<li>Oxford</li>
</settlement>
<orgName>
<li>Université d'Oxford</li>
</orgName>
</list>
<tree>
<country name="Royaume-Uni">
<noRegion>
<name sortKey="Shea, Nicholas" sort="Shea, Nicholas" uniqKey="Shea N" first="Nicholas" last="Shea">Nicholas Shea</name>
</noRegion>
<name sortKey="Bang, Dan" sort="Bang, Dan" uniqKey="Bang D" first="Dan" last="Bang">Dan Bang</name>
<name sortKey="Bang, Dan" sort="Bang, Dan" uniqKey="Bang D" first="Dan" last="Bang">Dan Bang</name>
<name sortKey="Boldt, Annika" sort="Boldt, Annika" uniqKey="Boldt A" first="Annika" last="Boldt">Annika Boldt</name>
<name sortKey="Frith, Chris D" sort="Frith, Chris D" uniqKey="Frith C" first="Chris D." last="Frith">Chris D. Frith</name>
<name sortKey="Heyes, Cecilia" sort="Heyes, Cecilia" uniqKey="Heyes C" first="Cecilia" last="Heyes">Cecilia Heyes</name>
<name sortKey="Yeung, Nick" sort="Yeung, Nick" uniqKey="Yeung N" first="Nick" last="Yeung">Nick Yeung</name>
</country>
<country name="Danemark">
<noRegion>
<name sortKey="Bang, Dan" sort="Bang, Dan" uniqKey="Bang D" first="Dan" last="Bang">Dan Bang</name>
</noRegion>
<name sortKey="Frith, Chris D" sort="Frith, Chris D" uniqKey="Frith C" first="Chris D." last="Frith">Chris D. Frith</name>
</country>
</tree>
</affiliations>
</record>

Pour manipuler ce document sous Unix (Dilib)

EXPLOR_STEP=$WICRI_ROOT/Ticri/CIDE/explor/HapticV1/Data/Ncbi/Merge
HfdSelect -h $EXPLOR_STEP/biblio.hfd -nk 002D43 | SxmlIndent | more

Ou

HfdSelect -h $EXPLOR_AREA/Data/Ncbi/Merge/biblio.hfd -nk 002D43 | SxmlIndent | more

Pour mettre un lien sur cette page dans le réseau Wicri

{{Explor lien
   |wiki=    Ticri/CIDE
   |area=    HapticV1
   |flux=    Ncbi
   |étape=   Merge
   |type=    RBID
   |clé=     PMC:3989995
   |texte=   Supra-personal cognitive control and metacognition
}}

Pour générer des pages wiki

HfdIndexSelect -h $EXPLOR_AREA/Data/Ncbi/Merge/RBID.i   -Sk "pubmed:24582436" \
       | HfdSelect -Kh $EXPLOR_AREA/Data/Ncbi/Merge/biblio.hfd   \
       | NlmPubMed2Wicri -a HapticV1 

Wicri

This area was generated with Dilib version V0.6.23.
Data generation: Mon Jun 13 01:09:46 2016. Site generation: Wed Mar 6 09:54:07 2024